Jump to content

Vicarious mediation and vicarious functioning

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Vicarious mediation is the potential level of substitutability in the task itself, the different potential ways (or mediational pathways) that exist for achieving an outcome or performing a task successfully. For example, what is the substitutability of potential cues for accurate judgments about the size of objects in a visual field, particularly when all the cues are not available or are not perfect predictors of size? Similarly, what is the substitutability of potential behaviors (or means) to accomplish one’s goals (or ends) when all actions may not be available or equally effective? The focus is on the task, the various potentially substitutable pathways mediating success in the task itself.

Background

[edit]

Expert judgment as well as everyday judgments require people to use known information to make a judgment about some unknown quantity or event. In judgment and decision research, the known information makes up the cues and the unknown quantity or event is called the criterion. In natural situations, the cues are generally related to each other and are only probabilistically related to the criterion.  As a result of interrelations among the cues, there is some degree of intersubstitutability among them, that is, one cue or set of cues can often be used in place of another. This property of intersubstitutability can be helpful in making judgments when, as is often the case, not all the cues that the person would want are actually available.

Anderson et. al.[1] note that “The mutual substitutability of cues is what system theorists (e.g., Karl Ludwig von Bertalanffy[2]) have called equipotentiality. … The mutual substitutability of responses … have been called equifinality.” (p. 248)

Anderson et al.[1] also point out that vicarious mediation is related to redundancy [engineering]. For example, in human factors engineering (e.g., Lee et al.[3]), redundancy gain is defined as presenting the same information through multiple channels to avoid confusion and ensure the information gets through, such as traffic lights using both color and position to convey, go, caution, and stop.

Vicarious functioning

[edit]

In contrast, vicarious functioning refers to substitutability regarding what people do, that is, the way they actually function. For example, vicarious functioning refers to which potentially substitutable cues are actually used, and how are they used, when people make judgments, particularly when all the cues are not available and are not perfect predictors of the criterion. What actions do people actually take to accomplish their goals, particularly when all actions are not available or equally effective? The focus is on the person, the various substitutable pathways they actually follow in an effort to function effectively.

Egon Brunswik[4] noted that Hunter[5][6] first introduced the term vicarious functioning; that vicarious functioning played a major role in the definition of purposeful behavior by William McDougall[7] and Edward C. Tolman;[8] that Clark L. Hull[9] incorporated the concept into his theory of habit-family-hierarchy; and that psychoanalytic mechanisms were an expression of vicarious functioning (e.g., see Else Frenkel-Brunswik[10]).

Importance of vicarious mediation and vicarious functioning in understanding achievement

[edit]

Both concepts, vicarious mediation (substitutability in the task) and vicarious functioning (substitutability by the person), are critical to Brunswik’s theory of probabilistic functionalism regarding how people can and, in fact, do function effectively (or not) in an uncertain or probabilistic world. Gigerenzer and Kurz[11] note, “Vicarious functioning describes adaptive cognitive processes that can handle two constraints: the presence of uncertainty and the need for substitution. A cue (e.g., the retinal image of an object) is only an uncertain indicator of a distal stimulus (e.g., the distance to the object), and a cue may not always be present; thus, an adaptive system has to rely on multiple cues that can be substituted for each other.” (pp. 342–343). To quote Kenneth. R. Hammond,[12] “the organism meets the vicarious mediation of the environment with vicarious functioning on its own part.” (p. 41). Both concepts, vicarious mediation in the task and vicarious functioning by the person, are essential to understanding achievement.

The concept of Ecological Rationality developed by Gerd Gigerenzer and his colleagues[13][14] also extends Brunswik’s theory of probabilistic functionalism (and the concepts of vicarious mediation and functioning). Its focus has been on understanding the simple judgment heuristics people use to combine cue information in different types of task environments.

When vicarious mediation is high, there are many potential substitutable pathways to success. The task itself provides different ways (or means) for people to succeed. Consequently, people can take different approaches to performing the task and still be successful. To take an extreme case, if two cues are perfectly correlated, then they will have equal ecological validity and, therefore, be fully redundant in predicting the outcome or distal variable (criterion) of interest. Assuming the cues have high ecological (or predictive) validities, a person need only use one of these two perfectly substitutable cues to predict successfully, and different people will be equally successful using different cues.  

However, when vicarious mediation is low, there are few (if any) substitutable pathways to success. Consequently, people must select as many valid pathways as they can to function effectively. To quote Brunswik,[4] “Proper cognitive adjustment demands (a) that vicarious utilization of many cues be present when validities are imperfect, and (b) that hierarchy of utilization (relative strength in rivalry) follow the hierarchy of validity.” (p. 308). Failure to select the multiple cues with the highest ecological validities will lead to lower achievement because the task itself has less flexibility and robustness when vicarious mediation is low.

There are many examples of vicarious mediation and vicarious functioning. As one example, Brunswik[15] showed that size constancy--the stable and successful prediction of object size (vicarious functioning)--was possible because of the substitutability of redundant perceptual cues in the task (vicarious mediation). In another example, Hammond[16] noted that, “When pigeons are unable to locate the sun because of cloud cover, magnetic lines of force function vicariously for the sun [to permit successful navigation].” (p. 115). Gigerenzer and Kurtz[11] showed that a simple judgment heuristic called Take the Best (using only the single best predicting cue) could be substituted for far more complex strategies and still maintain or even improve achievement under certain task conditions. And Adelman et. al.[17] showed that, under high vicarious mediation, teams can interact differently (vicarious functioning) under increasing time pressure and still maintain comparable achievement.

In putting forward the concepts of vicarious mediation and vicarious functioning, Brunswik highlighted the importance, from both a theoretical and methodological perspective, of studying the task as well as the person to understand achievement. Regarding the former, Brunswik developed the lens model to represent his theory of probabilistic functionalism pictorially. The left side of the lens model represented vicarious mediation, the pathways in the task. The right side represented vicarious functioning, what the person does to perform the task. Achievement was represented by an over-arching arrow linking the two sides, task and person. (Hursch, et al.[18] and Tucker[19] subsequently developed the lens model equation to represent Brunswik’s lens model mathematically.) The message was clear, one could not fully understand the effectiveness of individuals’ functional processes without understanding task characteristics.

From a methodological perspective, Brunswik advocated naturalistic research and the representative design of experiments to study achievement. To quote Brunswik[15] “… the study of functional person-environment relationships would seem to require that not only mediation but also focal events and other situational circumstances should be made to represent … the general or specific conditions under which the organism studied has to function.”(pp. 29–30) And to quote Hammond,[12] “… if we are to understand fully how organisms capable of vicarious functioning behave, we shall have to place them in situations that permit vicarious functioning to occur.” (p. 50). Both theory and method are critical to understanding the role of vicarious mediation and vicarious functioning in achievement.

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b Anderson, B. F., Deane, D. H., Hammond, K. R., McClelland, G. H., & Shanteau, J. C. (1981). Concepts in judgment and decision research: Definitions, sources, interrelation, comments. New York: Praeger.
  2. ^ von Bertalanffy, K. L. (1956). General systems theory. In General Systems, Yearbook of the Society for the Advancement of General Systems Theory (Vol. 1).
  3. ^ Lee, J. D., Wickens, C. D., Liu, Y., & Boyle, L. N. (2017). Designing for people: An introduction to human factors engineering. Charleston, S. C.: CreateSpace.
  4. ^ a b Brunswik, E. (1957). Scope and aspect of the cognitive problem. In K. R. Hammond & T. R. Stewart (Eds.), The essential Brunswik: Beginnings, explications, applications (pp. 300–312). New York: Oxford University Press.
  5. ^ Hunter, W. S. (1928). Human behavior. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  6. ^ Hunter, W. (1932). The psychological study of behavior. The Psychological Review, 39(1), 1-24.
  7. ^ McDougall, W. (1908). Introduction to social psychology. London: Methuen.
  8. ^ Tolman, E. C. (1932). Purposive behavior in animals. New York: Century.
  9. ^ Hull, C. L. (1934). The concept of the habit-family-hierarchy and maze learning. Psychological Review, 41, 33–54
  10. ^ Frenkel-Brunswik, E. (1949). Intolerance of ambiguity as an emotional and perceptional personality variable. Journal of Personality, 18, 108–143.
  11. ^ a b Gigerenzer, G. & Kurz, E. M. (2001). Vicarious functioning reconsidered: A fast and frugal lens model. In K. R. Hammond & T. R. Stewart (Eds.), The essential Brunswik: Beginnings, explications, applications (pp. 342–347). New York: Oxford University Press.
  12. ^ a b Hammond, K. R. (1966). Probabilistic functionalism: Egon Brunswik’s integration of the history, theory, and method of psychology. In K. R. Hammond (Ed.), The Psychology of Egon Brunswik (pp. 15–80). New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.
  13. ^ Gigerenzer, G., Todd, P. M., & The ABC Research Group (1999). Simple heuristics that make us smart. New York: Oxford University Press.
  14. ^ Todd, P. M., Gigerenzer, G., & The ABC Research Group (2012). Ecological rationality: Intelligence in the world. New York: Oxford University Press.
  15. ^ a b Brunswik, E. (1952). The conceptual framework of psychology (International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, Vol. 1, No. 10). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  16. ^ Hammond, K. R. (1996). Human judgment and social policy: Irreducible uncertainty, inevitable error, unavoidable injustice. NY: Oxford University Press.
  17. ^ Adelman, L., Miller, S., Henderson, D., & Schoelles, M. (2003). Using Brunswikian theory and a longitudinal design to study how hierarchical teams adapt to increasing levels of time pressure. Acta Psychologica, 112, 181–206.
  18. ^ Hursch, C. J., Hammond, K. R., & Hursch, J. L. (1964). Some methodological considerations in multiple-cue probability learning studies. Psychological Review, 71, 42–60.
  19. ^ Tucker, L. R. (1964). A suggested alternative formulation in the developments by Hursch, Hammond, & Hursch and by Hammond, Hursch, & Todd. Psychological Review, 71, 528–530.