User:B.Sirota/sandbox/Ver5
This is not a Wikipedia article: It is an individual user's work-in-progress page, and may be incomplete and/or unreliable. For guidance on developing this draft, see Wikipedia:So you made a userspace draft. Find sources: Google (books · news · scholar · free images · WP refs) · FENS · JSTOR · TWL |
NewVERS.12 22Dec24. The hypothesis of the bicameral ("two-chambered") mind is about the neurological basis of verbal hallucinations and their importance, especially in ancient history.[1][2][3][4] It asserts that hallucinated voices are caused by the brain's two-sided structure,[5] and that 'voice-hearing' without consciousness was the defining characteristic of human psychology in the world's first civilizations,[6] and also the natural cause of early supernatural concepts and religions.[7][8] The hypothesis is part of a far-reaching psycho-historical theory proposed by research psychologist Julian Jaynes in his 1976 book, The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind.[Note 1] Jaynes argues that consciousness,[a] correctly understood, is neither innate nor supernatural[b] but rather a learned behavior[10] which first occurred late in the 2nd millennium BCE and eventually displaced a “mentality based on verbal hallucinations".[2]: 452 Jaynes called that earlier mentality, which was somewhat similar to modern schizophrenia,[11] a bicameral mind because psychologically it had two parts, one 'god-like', one human,[3]: 88 but "neither part was conscious."[1]: 84 [4]: 8
Evidence is drawn from linguistics, ancient texts, archaeology, behavioral and comparative psychology, and clinical studies of schizophrenia and the so-called "split brain". Part of the argument is that ancient humans had sensations and language, and lived mostly habitually just as people do today, but they left no cultural evidence of any 'inner self' or 'conscious mind' because they had none, that is, they had not learned to introspect on their own actions and experiences. Instead, the ancient records are conspicuously about people 'hearing' one or more 'voices of authority' that commanded action, could not be disobeyed, and ruled over daily life.[12] Such "voices of chiefs, rulers or the gods"[13]: 1 were often associated with natural phenomena or hand-made 'divine' images.[14] In terms of the hypothesis, preconscious 'bicamerality' arose because the biological evolution of language involved both cerebral hemispheres (not just the left as per mainstream neurolinguistics theory[15]) such that the left hemisphere would 'hear' the right hemisphere 'speak' as though it were a separate, dominant being.[5]
The hypothesis potentially explains many "otherwise mysterious facts"[8]: 273 of ancient history such as idolatry, polytheism and oracles. Also many modern phenomena with varying degrees of trance or "diminished consciousness",: 324 such as hypnosis and severe schizophrenia, might be explainable as "vestiges" of ancient bicamerality (when the brain supposedly worked in a "more primitive"[1]: 432 way than today).[16][17] The hypothesis has influenced modern research into hallucinations in the general population[17] and today voice-hearing is not always judged as mental illness.[18][19][20][21] Groups such as the Hearing Voices Movement seek meaning in the experience[17] which is known to be reported in most, possibly all, cultures, often with a spiritual significance.[1]: 413 [18]: xi [22] Alternative hypotheses about voice-hearing, or auditory verbal hallucinations, have been proposed, but as of 2020, the phenomenon remains poorly understood both neurologically[23] and historically.[18][24]
Jaynes's overall theory, of an evolved bicamerality and of a later, learned consciousness, has been promoted as a "revolutionary idea" and a "new scientific paradigm"[c] that challenges common assumptions about human nature, mental health[25]: 126–131 and religion.[8] One early reviewer called it "ingenious [and] remarkable [... yet] exasperating [in its] incompleteness".[26]: 163 Based on "bold"[27]: 150 interpretations of the known facts, the theory has been described as largely unproveable.[18]: 35 [26]: 164 About Jaynes's approach to consciousness, one early critic rejected it as "absurd",[28] another as "biased" against evolution.[29] Supporters, while acknowledging that "Jaynes’s work is generally dismissed"[30]: 304 or "ignored"[13]: 2 by many experts, contend nevertheless (as of 2016) that Jaynes’s theorizing is "ahead of much of the current thinking in consciousness studies"[17][d] and that "critiques of the theory are [mostly] based on misconceptions about what Jaynes actually said".[33]
Context and overview
[edit]Jaynesian psycho-historical theory
[edit]The bicameral hypothesis was one of several components in a "large" psycho-historical[e] theory "covering so much of the terrain of human nature and history".[2]: 447 The theory came to public attention in 1977[f] in The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind, a book by Julian Jaynes (1920-1997), a respected lecturer and research psychologist at Princeton University from 1964 to 1995.[34] The book, his one and only, was written for general readers[g] on the results of "his lifelong work"[34]: 47 on the problem of consciousness.[34] The bicameral hypothesis, about the nature and importance of verbal hallucinations in early civilizations, emerged in the context of Jaynes's contention "that a civilization without consciousness is possible".[36]: 47
The 'problem' of consciousness
[edit]Early in the 1800's psychology was called "the science of consciousness"[37]: 364 and by century's end introspection was not only the main method of study but almost a synonym for consciousness.[37][h] This "traditional view defines consciousness as the direct awareness or immediate experience of the contents and processes of mind [and the] method of observing consciousness, so defined, is introspection".[37]: 365 During the 20th century the traditional view was early on ignored by many in favor of behaviorism[37]: 365 [39]: 13-16 then later on consciousness was defined as awareness[i] and was so studied through brain research. Although the traditional view had been widely abandoned, its problems had not been resolved.[37]: 365 [39]: 13-16 [j] One psychologist in 2006 rephrased the traditional problem as, "Just what is it that makes a brain seemingly "introspectable?""[10]: 174–175
Jaynes saw the problem of consciousness in traditional terms, affirming that its "denotative definition is, as it was for Descartes, Locke, and Hume, what is introspectable",[40]: 450 one's 'innermost sense of self'[39] and completely distinct from sensory perception.[40]: 447-449 Introspection is something like observation, but without a sensory organ, and whatever the 'mind's-eye' 'sees' is perhaps something 'mental',[k] but is certainly not the brain's internal reality. Jaynes argued that introspection is an 'inner sense' only metaphorically,[42] and the 'inner space' or 'inner world' of consciousness "must be a metaphor of real space."[42]: 54 Jaynes wrote that "Subjective conscious mind is an analog of what is called the real world",[42]: 55 something like a map, and "through metaphorical language"[9]: 1 it is 'built' first, and then 'operates' through linguistic or visual metaphors and analogies.[2]: 452 His main claims include: that most of the time people act habitually without consciousness, since it is irrelevant for most behavior but can help to "shortcut behavioral processes and arrive at more adequate decisions";[42]: 55 that "there is no operation in consciousness that did not occur in behavior first";[2]: 449 that consciousness is not neural state or process but a way of using language; it is "learned and not innate";[9]: 6 [10] and is therefore created by culture rather than evolution.[25]: 96 Consciousness has several distinct features (e.g. mind-space and narratization) which can vary between cultures, and children can learn these at a late stage of language acquisition, but only through socialization.[43] Jaynes's view influenced later social constructivist theorists such as Daniel Dennett.[27]
Historical origin of consciousness
[edit]Jaynes also hypothesized that consciousness had an historical origin about 3,000 years ago, late in the 2nd millenium BCE.[l] On his analysis, there is no clear evidence of interiority or introspection before that era.[44] He argued that consciousness was a cultural "invention"[34]: 36 like agriculture and writing, a "new mentality": 257 that became possible "only after the breakdown"[2]: 453 of an older, non-conscious mentality and cultural system.[12][45] The breakdown of the older mentality was not a specific, one-time event, but a gradual process stretched over centuries. Certain processes of language change were involved in the historical origin of consciousness,[46]: 216-222 [47][48] and other social processes allowed it to spread across cultures or be learned by children.
Before consciousness
[edit]Jaynes further hypothesized that before the ancient origin of consciousness, human mentality was in fact hallucinatory, with a divided psychology caused by the way language evolved in the brain, which according to Jaynes must have occurred in both cerebral hemispheres. He came to call it a bicameral (i.e. "two-chambered") mind as "...a rather inexact metaphor to a bicameral legislature of an upper and lower house."[3]: 88 The idea of a "preconscious mentality",: 397 one that was, moreover, based on verbal hallucinations, was so extraordinary that, in anticipation of readers' reactions, Jaynes himself introduced it (with obvious irony) as "preposterous".: 84 Nevertheless, the bicameral hypothesis was intended to explain, as scientifically as possible,[m] a wide range of important facts of the early history of civilizations and religions.[7]
Mind and culture
[edit]The transition from bicamerality toward consciousness is considered an on-going historical process affecting all of human culture.[50] Since the middle of the 1st millenium BCE, consciousness has flourished and interacted with "the rest of cognition"[2]: 456 to expand human abilities and accelerate cultural change. Meanwhile, the continuing legacy of the bicameral mentality is evident mainly in religious traditions with ancient roots, but also in a variety of persistent forms of "diminished consciousness": 324 or some degree of trance, which might all share a common genetic and neurological basis in the two-hemisphere structure of the human brain.[16] In the modern world, many phenomena may crucially involve "right hemisphere function in a way that is different from ordinary conscious life" and may in some cases involve "a partial periodic right hemisphere dominance".: 324–325 Only some are hallucinatory, yet all might be "vestiges of the bicameral mind".[16][n] Examples of possible vestigiality are: music and poetry;[51] prophecy, spiritual possession, and glossolalia;[52] hypnosis;[53] schizophrenia;[11] shamanism;[54] and "the 'invisible playmates' of childhood; [...] and hundreds more."[55]
Implications and significance
[edit]The bicameral hypothesis touches a "staggering" range of subjects,[o] and has many "far-reaching"[55] implications:
- the evolution of language involved both sides of the brain, and the organization of language in the brain is changeable;[5]
- the first verbal hallucinations might have been "a side effect of language comprehension which evolved by natural selection as a method of behavioral control": 134 for early small groups;
- the bicameral system of social control and organization enabled the first agricultural civilizations wherever they arose;[57][6][p]
- bicamerality can explain "our first ideas of gods"[58] as evident in the polytheism, idolatry, and theocracy of ancient societies worldwide;[7][8]: 281–286
- the "weakening": 228 of bicameral 'voices', in part by the invention of writing, can explain the 2nd millennium BCE beliefs in demons and angels which served as "hybrid human-animal": 230 intermediaries to the gods; these supernatural beings were later supplemented by spiritualistic and magical practices, such as divination, incantation of spells, amulets, prayers, and oracles, etc., all aimed at invoking, appeasing or replacing the increasingly absent or unreliable gods;[47][59]
- the inherent instabilities of bicamerality might explain both the slow pace of growth during the early millennia of civilized society, as well as the rapid social breakdown of the 'Bronze age collapse';[60]
In the final chapter of Jaynes’s book[61] he philosophically interpreted the long cultural transition from bicamerality. Jaynes wonders, "Why should we demand that the universe make itself clear to us? Why do we care?": 433 Noting that "the urgency behind mankind’s yearning for divine certainties": 435 is recorded as the "drama . . . of the central intellectual tendency of world history",: 436 he argues that all modern religious, pseudo-religious and superstitious systems, including "faith in various pseudosciences",: 440 spring from the same psychological discomforts felt when bicameral voices were originally lost. Modern science can also exhibit "the same quasi-religious gestures" and generate "scientisms [... or] scientific mythologies which fill the very felt void left by the divorce of science and religion in our time.": 441 The historical "secularization of science": 437 expresses the "erosion of the religious view of man [that has been and] is still a part of the breakdown of the bicameral mind.": 439 For Jaynes, religion exists and persists not for metaphysical reasons but because it is rooted in the brain.[62] In 1978, interviewer Richard Rhodes[63] quoted Jaynes, as follows, on the historical relationship between bicamerality and religion:
One of the things I’m trying to protect, […] by identifying its sources, is the function of religion in the world today. The voices are silent. True. But the brain is organized in a religious fashion. Our mentalities have come out of a divine kind of mind.
Consciousness, by contrast, is given a non-metaphysical but also non-evolutionary origin that marks a "radical discontinuity"[62]: 180 between humans and the rest of nature. The "archaic authorization": 320 for civilized action originally came from culturally dependent voice-hearing that controlled behavior, but having broken down, it would to a great degree be replaced by cultivated selfhood, self-control and moral responsibility. As Jaynes put it:[64]: 79
[V]oices which had to be obeyed were the absolute prerequisite to the conscious stage of mind in which it is the self that is responsible and can debate within itself, can order and direct, [and] the creation of such a self is the product of culture.
Yet such a 'self' is psychologically suggestible and can be displaced, often in trance-like, obedient service to a 'higher power' (e.g. a hypnotist, demagogue, 'demon', or voice): Jaynes proposed a general bicameral paradigm[50]: 323-328 to explain this social process that often "allows a more absolute control over behavior than is possible with consciousness."[53]: 379
Reception and influence
[edit]Jaynes's arguments and conclusions were called "ingenious" and "remarkable", yet also "exasperating" and "incomplete".[q] Some early commentators noted that the arguments for bicamerality are difficult to summarize and explain without "distorting" Jaynes's theory or making it "difficult to take seriously."[r]
Richard Rhodes commented in 1978: "Jaynes's theories…are radical, though well within the traditions of science — he is no Velikovsky or von Daniken bending the facts to sweeten preconception."[63] In 1986, Daniel Dennett argued that Jaynes had sought to maintain "plausibility" acceptable to scientific standards, even though his project was a necessarily "bold" and "speculative exercise" to fill unavoidable gaps in the historical data. It risked the "dangers" of making huge mistakes because it combined an "amalgam of […] thinking about how it had to be, historical sleuthing [for relevant facts], and inspired guesswork".(Dennett's italics)[68]
David Stove wrote in 1989 that Jaynes's "controversial and provocative" theory was "that rarest of things: an absolutely original idea…of most various and far-reaching consequences".[55] Regarding bicamerality and the possibility that humanity experienced an historic change of mentality, Stove commented that "…if such a thing had happened, an astounding number of otherwise mysterious facts would receive an explanation!"[69] and Stove added that "Jaynes has made a definite suggestion, where no one else had a single thing to offer" to explain the existence of religion.[70]
The broad scope of Jaynes's argument, evidence and conclusions has been one reason for academic caution and reservation of judgement[s] as well as a possible reason for hostility from scientists.[t] Jaynes's use of ancient texts as evidence was another reason for academic caution or skepticism.[u]
The complexity of Jaynes's "multi-disciplinary" theorizing has been seen as a reason that his work has been more ignored than tested or refuted.[13]: 2 One commentator noted that among early critics of Jaynes’s proposals, "everyone could find a topic or conjecture that they disagreed with".[73] If some have indeed ignored Jaynes, the bicameral hypothesis has nevertheless been described as "undoubtedly influential" by Daniel B. Smith in his 2007 book on "rethinking" auditory hallucinations, where he commented that "... perhaps the only thing that [Jaynes's] boosters and critics agree upon is that [bicamerality] can't be proved."[74] Smith argued that Jaynes's theory matters, whether it is correct or not, because "the problem of voice-hearing is in large part indistinguishable from the problem of consciousness, and that the relationship between the two has been fruitful in determining the attributes of each."[74]
Philosophers have been divided in the extreme in their attitude to Jaynes and his ideas. Cavanna et.al. (2007) wrote: "Overall, the attitude of philosophers of mind towards the plausibility of a bicameral mind has been controversial."[75] Philosopher Jan Sleutels in 2006 argued in support of plausibility, but noted that "Jaynes's established repute is now such that the merest association with his views causes suspicion"[76] and commented:[31]
In philosophy [Jaynes] is rarely mentioned and almost never taken seriously. The only notable exception is Daniel Dennett who appreciates Jaynes as a fellow social constructivist with regard to consciousness. Most outspoken in his criticism is Ned Block, who rejects Jaynes's claim as patently absurd.
From an atheist viewpoint, Richard Dawkins in 2006 considered Jaynes's arguments and described his book as "either complete rubbish or a work of consummate genius, nothing in between! Probably the former, but I'm hedging my bets. [...] Whether or not you find his thesis plausible, Jaynes's book is intriguing enough to earn its mention in a book on religion."[77]
Over the years Jaynes's ideas have attracted continuous public attention and occasional academic "reappraisal"[78] or "defense".[79] Researchers have acknowledged that Jaynes was a pioneer in the modern study of consciousness and that his bicameral hypothesis has had "widespread influence",[v] especially regarding the idea of separate roles for each cerebral hemisphere.[80] The hypothesis "inspired much of the modern research into hallucinations in the normal population [since] the early 1980s"[17] and today voice-hearing is not always judged as mental illness.[18][19][20][21] Groups such as the Hearing Voices Movement seek meaning in the experience[17] which has ancient forms such as "the prophetic phenomenon" of Biblical Israel[22] and is known to be reported in most, possibly all, cultures, often with religious or spiritual significance.[1]: 413 [18]: xi [81]
The Julian Jaynes Society was founded in 1997, after Jaynes's death, to promote awareness of his work and theories. They maintain a website with a collection of relevant research,[45] and have published collections of essays on related topics. Its founder, Marcel Kuijsten argued in 2016 that Jaynes’s theorizing "continues to be ahead of much of the current thinking in consciousness studies",[17][w] "remains the most supportable and generalizable explanation for the occurrence of auditory hallucinations, and provides voice-hearers with a historical context to better understand their experience."[83] Kuijsten contends that "the vast majority of critiques of the theory are based on misconceptions about what Jaynes actually said".[33]
Section Notes
[edit]- ^ There is no single definition of the term 'consciousness', nor consensus about what phenomena it refers to. In relation to the hypothesis of the bicameral mind, consciousness is not perception but "what is introspectable."[2]: 450
- ^ "Jaynes demonstrates that consciousness is not an all or nothing proposition, but rather a package of features that are learned and thus can vary in different individuals and cultures. [It ...] is learned and not innate".[9]: 6
- ^ Quotations are from the 1990 edition book-cover.[2]
- ^ The Jaynesian approach is social constructivist,[31] and differs from the concepts, goals and methods of cognitive science and neuroscience.[32]
- ^ Jaynes uses the term psycho-historian: 211 (also psycho-archaeology: 177 ) in reference to the history of human mentality in general, not to an individual's psychohistory as the term is used in psychoanalysis.
- ^ The original copyright is from 1976, but the book was not released until mid-January 1977.[34]: 42
- ^ William Woodward, in reviewing the book as a historian of psychology, noted: "The historian of science…must approach [the book] on the level of a popular scientific document which makes use of history" and "the book certainly succeeds in meeting this presentist goal."[35]: 293
- ^ From the MacMillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 1967: "Locke's use of 'consciousness' was widely adopted in British philosophy. In the late nineteenth century the term 'introspection' began to be used. G. F. Stout's definition is typical: "To introspect is to attend to the workings of one's own mind" [... (1899)]."[38]: 191–192
- ^ The equation of consciousness with awareness or perception became popular in the 20th century. The basic definition of the term 'consciousness' as wakefulness came into use during the 19th century.[37]
- ^ "But even if the traditional theory is wrong, something like introspection often takes place."[38]: 193
- ^ The mind's presumed knowledge of itself has been questioned, for example by independent research from as early as 1977 described as the introspection illusion.[41]
- ^ The dating is always an approximation, for example in Kuijsten, "as recently as 3,000 years ago",[9]: 1 or "around 1200 B.C."[25]: 106
- ^ See comments under #Reception and influence: [49][27][8]
- ^ While bicamerality was without consciousness, vestigial phenomena are problematic in that "the trance state of narrowed or absent consciousness is not ... a duplicate of the bicameral mind.": 339
- ^ Philosopher David Stove wrote in 1989 that Jaynes "touches, at greater or less length, on a staggering number and variety of subjects, concerning which his theory has implications …"[8]: 271
One example of an explicit list is from James Morriss (1978): "…neurophysiology, anthropology, classical literature, psychopathology, ancient history, general semantics, art, and poetry."[56]: 317 - ^ "The bicameral mind produced a new kind of social control that allowed agricultural civilizations to begin."[3]: 88
- ^ See Etkin, 1977, p.163: "…it has been a long time since I read anything in the problem of human evolution that was at once so stimulating with original insights and ingenious interpretations yet disappointing, even exasperating, by the incompleteness of its analysis."[26]: 163 Also Marriott, 1980, p.158: "Many questions are raised and remain unanswered… But whether or not the concept of 'bicameral' civilization is convincing, this is a remarkable book. I cannot in this brief review do justice to [Jaynes's] teeming ideas";[65] Woodward, 1979: "…this extraordinary book which defies disciplinary classification…is noteworthy as a primary source which challenges mental evolutionists…[and which] marshalls literary and archaeological evidence for a question central to language, religion, and science — the origin of consciousness."[35]: 292
- ^ See Marriott, 1980, p.158: "I cannot in this brief review do justice to [Jaynes's] teeming ideas, to the range of his learning in half a dozen disciplines. His arguments are inevitably simplified and distorted here."[65] Also Morriss, 1978, p.316: "Unaccompanied by Jaynes's arguments and evidence, a brief explanation of his thesis is inadequate";[66] and Etkin, 1977: "Stated thus briefly without illustrations [Jaynes's] argument is difficult to take seriously."[67]
- ^ Woodward, 1979, p.293: "One is tempted to reserve judgement on such a daring thesis as this, realizing that it demands an impossibly broad range of knowledge to endorse or refute."[71]
- ^ Jones, 1979, p.23: "…all probably agree that, the more inclusive the hypothesis, the looser the fit [with evidence] is likely to be, [and] we ought to be willing to tolerate a certain looseness of fit in hypotheses of very great scope. …neurologists, archaeologists, linguists and psychologists might make…differential assessments of the [evidence] that reflect a differential tolerance for looseness of fit on the part of the scientists concerned. Nevertheless, and taking Mr. Jaynes' argument as a whole, I also predict that the reaction of most scientists would be skeptical if not hostile."[72]
- ^ Etkin, p. 164: "To one trained to look for objective evidence such [literary analysis] carries no strong conviction, especially since even superficial acquaintance with the sources suggests much that does not fit into the author's pattern… Few students of behavior venture this path."[67]
- ^ Cavanna, et al. (2007): "Jaynes' thought-provoking and pioneering work in the field of consciousness studies gave rise to a longlasting debate[;]"[78]: 11 and "Jaynes' composite picture of the bicameral mind has had widespread influence and undoubtedly shaped to a considerable extent subsequent reflections on the biological and cultural underpinnings of human consciousness."[78]: 13
- ^ The Jaynesian approach stands apart from that of 'consciousness studies' which focuses on phenomena and concepts that "in Jaynes's view...are inappropriate targets for the word consciousness."[82]
Argument and evidence
[edit]The bicameral hypothesis, that there once was a mentality different from consciousness and it was all about 'gods' who were hallucinations, is an inference from "multiple independent sources of evidence"[84] which can be interpreted in many ways.
Possibility of a preconscious mentality
[edit]The Jaynesian idea, that humans could, and at one time did, live without consciousness (i.e. introspection, or "interiority"[85]), is not easy to understand or explain.[a]
Introspection, which for Jaynes is the sole basis of any "conception of what consciousness is,": 18 identifies "a succession of different conditions which I have been taught to call thoughts, images, memories, interior dialogues, regrets, wishes, resolves, all interweaving with the constantly changing pageant of exterior sensations of which I am selectively aware.": 23 Such are the 'contents' of recalling, reminiscing or reflecting on experience and behavior, or imagining past and future possibilities.[b] All these, however, are "a much smaller part of our mental life than we are conscious of, because we cannot be conscious of what we are not conscious of [...] !"[36]: 23 Behaviorism and experimental psychology in the 20th century have shown that much of human activity, like that of other animals, involves physiological processes that are mostly automatic and habitual. One can acquire scientific knowledge that such neural and cognitive processes exist and 'be conscious' of them when 'reflecting' on them, even though they cannot be experienced.[36][c]
Jaynes criticized "superficial views of consciousness that are embedded both in popular belief and in language"[2]: 447 which treat it as 'all of mentality' or as "that vaguest of terms, experience";: 8 or they fail to distinguish "between what is introspectable and all the hosts of other neural abilities we have come to call cognition"[2]: 447 including processes of awareness (which he called "reactivity": 22 ), attention, perception, and automatic learning, problem-solving or decision-making which all happen either without any experience of the process, or before any consciousness of the result.[9]: 8–9 [89]: 20–30 Not only is consciousness far less of mentality than is commonly supposed, it is neither a constant nor necessary condition for most behavior;[d] nevertheless our "consciousness of consciousness" seems to provide knowledge of what is called one's 'inner self' and one's own 'conscious mind'.[36]
It was the idea of interiority[39]: 9 [e] — of the mind as a 'space' filled with 'mental entities' or 'mental events' — that Jaynes defined as the "primary feature" among several[f] that comprise the "basic connotative definition of consciousness."[g] When people speak about private thoughts, or 'mental life', it is simply a part of what it means to be conscious to speak as if there is a "mind-space inside our own heads as well as the heads of others".[42]: 60 The 'mental activities' that supposedly occur 'in the mind', like all human physical activities, certainly involve the brain, but nobody has direct experience of their brain at work, and introspection can never reveal how the brain works (i.e. nerve impulses, synapses, etc.). Phrases like the 'inner world' or 'mind's eye' of introspection refer to the mind and its 'contents', not the brain; however, the mind can only be described or talked about with words that normally describe the 'external' physical world,[h] as Jaynes puts it:[4]: 6
Every word we use to refer to mental events is a metaphor or analog of something in the behavioral world.
Jaynes explains further that it is generally through the use of metaphors that people feel that they understand anything at all,[i] and he develops an original theory of metaphor to explain how the assumed mind-space and other features of consciousness operate. By assuming and speaking of the existence of a 'mind', 'soul', 'inner world' or 'inner self', people learn to act and to explain everyone's behavior as if caused or controlled by something 'on the inside'.[46]: 217 [j]
Furthermore, if consciousness is based on linguistic metaphors and analogs, then it can only be a human ability, and can emerge only at a certain level of linguistic and social complexity.[43] Therefore, says Jaynes, consciousness cannot be innate, and is a product of language and culture, not biological evolution.[k] And if it is not a necessary part of human psychology, then a society could have once existed with people "who spoke, judged, reasoned, solved problems" and more, without ever having learned to be conscious at all.[36]: 46-47
Four clues from history and psychology
[edit]The oldest 'mind words'
[edit]Jaynes notes that if the earliest remnants of the invention of writing can be deciphered at all, correct translation requires much scholarly guesswork based on facts from other bodies of knowledge. He argues that the standard approach of translators is to apply modern psychological ideas when trying to understand ancient mysterious facts, a method which naively assumes that human psychology thousands of years ago was fundamentally the same as it is today. Jaynes writes:[93]: 177
When the terms are concrete, as they usually are, for most of the cuneiform literature is receipts or inventories or offerings to the gods, there is little doubt of the correctness of translation. But as the terms tend to the abstract, and particularly when a psychological interpretation is possible, then we find well-meaning translators imposing modern categories to make their translations comprehensible [... and] to make ancient men seem like us[.]
The presence of consciousness in the past can only be inferred,[10]: 185–186 and only when certain words are in a context referring to the existence or acts of a person’s 'inner' being. Contrary to ordinary assumptions, Jaynes argues that no words for 'the mind' as we understand it today are found at all in the oldest texts, especially those that are well-understood, such as Greek[48] and Hebrew.[94]: 296 [l]
Example: The Iliad
[edit]The Iliad, an epic poem based on oral traditions from the 12th century BCE, was written down about 400 years later, and may be "the earliest writing […] in a language that [modern readers] can really comprehend".[64]: 82 Jaynes analyzes this well-studied source of Greek mythology, and makes the case that the oldest parts, in Homeric Greek, tell nothing of an 'inner life', which allows the possibility that at one time it did not exist. In Jaynes's words:[64]: 75
Iliadic man did not have subjectivity as do we; he had no awareness of his awareness of the world, no internal mind-space to introspect upon.
Bruno Snell made a similar point: "...there is in Homer no genuine reflexion, no dialogue of the soul with itself."[95][m] This contrasts with late classical Greek literature of the middle 1st millennium BCE.[48][96] Jaynes emphasizes that the Greek words with mental meanings in later centuries are originally, in the Iliad, always concrete, referring to limbs, organs or bodily actions; Jaynes analyzes key terms, including psyche, noos, thumos, phren, mermerizein, (also soma)… [48]: 69–71 and theorizes how they eventually transformed into mental words.[48]: 257-272 [n]
The 'gods' preceded 'mind'
[edit]Without the use of mental vocabulary, the Iliad explicitly depicts its human heroes as being stirred into action by ‘gods’, and they explain their own behavior as caused by gods who themselves take part in the action. The humans never "sit down and think out what to do".: 72 Jaynes considers that these interactions between gods and ordinary humans are similar to modern hallucinations, which are reported as 'voices', most often by people diagnosed with psychosis.[97]: 85-94
This "suggests": 75 an entirely new interpretation of the 'mythological' content and the epic poetry form of the Iliad: that the Homeric gods were not simply imaginative poetic devices, and Greek society before the 5th century BCE took the gods seriously;[o] furthermore, that in the late Bronze Age and for centuries into the early Iron Age, those who recited or heard the heroic tales accepted the reality of the gods because people commonly experienced god-voices in their own hallucinatory way. The Iliad becomes for Jaynes "a psychological document of immense importance",[64]: 69 providing one ancient clue to the hallucinatory mentality that he calls the "bicameral mind".[p]
Modern hallucinated voices
[edit]Based partly on his own clinical work and research, Jaynes argues that by the mid-20th century, the little that was scientifically known about verbal hallucinations had been learned mostly during the medical treatment of psychosis and schizophrenia.[1]: 87-88 [11] He recognizes that 'voices' have been generally feared as a sign of insanity requiring treatment, although in some cases they "may be helpful to the healing process";: 88 and they may have been the source of inspiration to "those who have in the past claimed such special selection": 86 as to hear voices of prophecy. Hallucinated voices may be "heard by completely normal people to varying degrees […] often in times of stress [or] on a more continuing basis."[97]: 86 Voices occur in all age-groups, come from any location and from every direction, and even "profoundly deaf schizophrenics insisted they had heard some kind of communication.": 91 The experience is varied and complex:[97]: 88-89
The voices in schizophrenia take any and every relationship to the individual. They converse, threaten, curse, criticize, consult, often in short sentences. They admonish, console, mock, command, or sometimes simply announce everything that's happening. They yell, whine, sneer, and vary from the slightest whisper to a thunderous shout. Often the voices take on some special peculiarity, such as speaking very slowly, scanning, rhyming, or in rhythms, or even in foreign languages. There may be one particular voice, more often a few voices, and occasionally many. [They] are recognized as gods, angels, devils, enemies, or a particular person or relative. Or occasionally they are ascribed to some kind of apparatus reminiscent of the statuary which we will see was important in this regard in bicameral kingdoms.
Medical cases differ in degrees of severity. But why are voices at all "believed, why obeyed"? Because "the voices a patient hears are more real than the doctor's voice.": 95 It is normal for healthy, conscious humans to be highly attentive and compliant to 'real' voices of those in recognized authority, especially when the voices are located nearby, and sound is a modality that cannot be shut out. Hallucinated voices cannot be silenced by force of will and if they can be resisted it is only with struggle, even if they command harmful or self-destructive behavior (as so-called command hallucinations often do). In less severe cases, some patients "learn to be objective toward them and to attenuate their authority […though at first there is always] unquestioning submission […] to the commands of the voices."[97]: 98
Language and the cerebral hemispheres
[edit]If the ‘hearing of voices’ has any physiological basis at all, then it has something to do with the way language is organized in the brain.[5]: 100 Jaynes acknowledges and reviews the known facts of his day showing that language is essentially a function of one cerebral hemisphere, most commonly the left.[q] He asks why this should be so, and why "those areas on the right hemisphere corresponding to the speech areas of the left" should seem to have “no easily observable major function”, yet can, under certain conditions, take over partial or full language functions. Jaynes speculates about the evolution of "their important function, since it must have been such to preclude [right hemisphere] development as an auxiliary speech area[.]"(original italics)[5]: 102-103
Research by Wilder Penfield from the 1950's showed that 'voices' could be 'heard' by patients when the right cerebral cortex was electrically stimulated.[5]: 106-112
Ground-breaking 1960s studies of the so-called "split brain"[r] showed that the two hemispheres can behave with a great deal of apparent independence, and while the right hemisphere can understand language, only the left (dominant) hemisphere seems to be associated with a person's self-identity.: 112–117
Jaynes incorporates such evidence to support the “tentative”: 103 possibility that verbal hallucinations generally come from the language areas of the right cerebral hemisphere and would sound to the left hemisphere as if spoken by another being.[5]
Aspects of Jaynes's hypothesis
[edit]Bicameral mind and bicameral society
[edit]The existence and character of the ancient system are "demonstrated in the literature and artifacts of antiquity."[40]: 456 The bicameral mind is describable, however, only by comparison to modern consciousness and especially modern hallucinations, about which too little is known.[s] Other than what people say of their experience, there is no explicit, objective method to verify the existence or character of hallucinations that seem externally real, just as the same is true of an 'inner life' of consciousness.
A divine mentality
[edit]The preposterous hypothesis we have come to is that at one time human nature was split in two, an executive part called a god, and a follower part called a man. Neither part was conscious. This is almost incomprehensible to us. And since we are conscious, [we] wish to understand[.][97]: 84
In distinction to our own subjective conscious minds, we can call the mentality of the Myceneans [and their era] a bicameral mind. Volition, planning, initiative is organized with no consciousness whatever and then 'told' to the individual in his familiar language, sometimes with the visual aura of a familiar friend or authority figure or 'god', or sometimes as a voice alone. The individual obeyed these hallucinated voices because he could not 'see' what to do by himself.[64]: 75
For this [hypothesis], the evidence is overwhelming. Wherever we look in antiquity, there is some kind of evidence that supports it [...] Apart from this theory, why are there gods? Why religions? Why does all ancient literature seem to be about gods and usually heard from gods?[40]: 452
The hallucinatory roots of civilization
[edit]The bicameral mind is ... that form of social control which allowed mankind to move from small hunter-gatherer groups to large agricultural communities. [It] evolved as a final stage of the evolution of language [in which] lies the origin of civilization.[6]: 126
Human group-life and language evolved together.[6] Pre-historic groups were small, their patterns of behavior were simple, and they "moved through their lives on the basis of habit — just as we do" today.[3]: 88 While language was simple and vocabulary was still too concrete for consciousness, the ancients "knew what followed what and where they were, and had behavioral expectancies and sensory recognitions just as all mammals do".[40]: 456 While routine behaviors would have been manageable by the vocal commands of a living parent or leader, repeatedly given as needed, social cohesion would be enhanced by the ability to recall the leader's commands.
The first hallucinated 'voices' may have been echoes of real vocal signals that evolved along with language comprehension to allow long-term behavioral control.[6]: 134–135 Larger groups, however, required more than the simple hallucinated memory of a leader's commands: the 'voices' "could with time improvise and 'say' things that the king himself had never said", just as "the 'voices' heard by contemporary schizophrenics 'think' as much and often more than they do[.]"[6]: 141
Before about 9000 BCE "voices would have played a minor role"[100] but provided the "system of social control"[84] that enabled the more complex life of settlements and agriculture in the first civilizations. This was the case in the oldest civilizations until about 1000 BCE, after which voices became a "hindrance".[100] Such was the case also in different parts of the world and in younger civilizations where the "advance to consciousness occurred quite late" (as perhaps occurred among the Incas after "their conquest by Pizarro").[56]: fn.28
Social control by 'voices'
[edit]Although modern, and presumably ancient, hallucinated voices occur within the individual's brain, they usually sound as 'real' and external as any human voice, and are often more authoritative.[81] Jaynes claimed about schizophrenia that:[11]: 409–410
... auditory hallucinations in general are not even slightly under the control of the individual [patient], but they are extremely susceptible to even the most innocuous suggestion from the total social circumstances of which the individual is a part. In other words, [...] hallucinations are dependent on the teachings and expectations of childhood — as we have postulated was true in bicameral times.
Hallucinations are thus dependent on cultural context as well as neurology.[18][81] This applies to modern voice-hearers (who live in a world of consciousness) and especially to schizophrenic patients who struggle with "hallucinations that are unacceptable and denied as unreal" by others.: 432 Bicameral people, however, lacked consciousness and could neither 'see for themselves' nor, for lack of an 'inner self', could they 'tell themselves' what to do; and, for lack of a culture of consciousness, they could not have deduced, imagined or even made sense of the modern idea that such voices 'came from their own heads'.
The archaeological record of the most well-understood early civilized societies and kingdoms, when they were stable, presents a rigid hierarchic structure, with divine beings at the top; the bicameral interpretation is that everybody relied on voices of authority, whether they were from a real person or a hallucinated divinity, that told the individual what to do. Civilized life, which Jaynes described as "the art of living in towns of such size that everyone does not know everyone else",[7]: 149 required bicameral authoritarianism, but he argued it was not oppressive:[46]: 205
...the bicameral mind was the social control, not fear or repression or even law. There were no private ambitions, no private grudges, no private frustrations, no private anything, since bicameral men had no internal 'space' in which to be private, and no analog 'I' to be private with. All initiative was in the voices of gods. And the gods needed to be assisted by their divinely dictated laws only in the late federations of states in the second millennium B.C.
Within each bicameral state, therefore, the people were probably more peaceful and friendly than in any civilization since.
Experiencing bicameral voices
[edit]In the modern world, occasions of learned conscious thinking are normal events in the context of otherwise habitual life;[t] when hallucinations occur, they are often "triggered by stressful, confusing, or "fight or flight" situations."[101] In bicameral times, when habitual, repetitive activities presumably dominated life, the threshold for psychological stress was probably much lower than today. Any decision-making situation, where "a change in behavior was necessary because of some novelty",[97]: 93 or where a problem was somewhat too complicated for normal habits, "was probably sufficient"[4] to trigger a voice.
Bicameral decision-making, an entirely unconscious process, was based on a lifetime of "admonitory experiences", i.e. being told by others what to do.: 93–94 A bicameral voice did not reason or 'think out loud' (as conscious people do) to solve a problem or make a decision. The 'voice' simply conveyed the result of non-concious, automatic processes of the nervous system: 37, 40, 42 in the form of a message or command. Today, the outcomes of similar processes are sometimes evident in the content of a person's consciousness, while consciousness is falsely deemed to be the source of the decision. In bicamerality, the habitual conditioning by accumulated experiences and the general social order could generate an admonitory 'voice'.[44]: 36–44
When the ancient individual heard a voice speaking a command, the command was authoritative and could not be disobeyed because it expressed the brain's unconscious volition.[44]: 98–99 However, at no time could a 'voice' be described or dismissed as 'one's own': for the bicameral human with no mind-space or conscious self-identity, there was no ability to judge the wisdom of the received messages, and disobedience would be literally unthinkable. Jaynes wrote:[97]: 98
. . . if one belonged to a bicameral culture, where the voices were recognized as at the utmost top of the hierarchy, taught you as gods, kings, majesties that owned you, head, heart, and foot, the omniscient, omnipotent voices that could not be categorized as beneath you, how obedient to them the bicameral man!
A visual component
[edit]Besides the stress of decision-making, certain sounds, such as wind and waves, might have had hallucinogenic effects in bicameral times, and so too could many visual stimuli, such as awe-inspiring vistas, clouds, sea mists, strange lighting and shadows, drawings, carved images, and ritual objects including stone idols.[14] Visual hallucinations are less commonly reported than auditory, but when they occur with voices, usually "they are merely shining light or cloudy fog",: 91–93 and they often have "flitting and bird-like movements.": 193
The Jaynesian "double brain" model of hallucinations
[edit]In the 1990 edition of his book, Jaynes specified that his psycho-historical theory consists of four "separable" hypotheses.[40]: 456 They are: the nature of consciousness; the dating of the 'dawn of consciousness'; the existence and character of the preconscious bicameral mind; and the proposed neurological model for hallucinations. Of the four hypotheses, his "double brain" neurological model for 'voices' is the one that is theoretically testable, but Jaynes knew "it would be decades before...his ideas could be tested."[102]
The neurological model underlying the bicameral mind was inspired by mid-20th-century discoveries about the cerebral hemispheres. The important and surprising facts included that both sides could comprehend language while only the left controlled speech, and that 'voices' could be 'heard' by electrical stimulation of the right hemisphere's cerebral cortex.[5]: 106-112 So-called "split brain" studies, especially, were not only demonstrating the conditional independence of the hemispheres,: 112–117 but were also generating much popular and scientific discussion about altered and complementary "modes of consciousness" (e.g. propositional/appositional, verbal/visuospatial, analytic/holistic) that were possibly related to the duality of the cerebral hemispheres.[103][u]
Jaynes assumed that modern language functions are normally localized and lateralized in the left hemisphere, but he hypothesized that archaic processes of language communication between the hemispheres could provide a neurological explanation to support his bicameral hypothesis.[5]
Bicameral and non-bicameral hallucinations
[edit]Jaynes's neurological model is meant to explain ancient hallucinations primarily, on the assumption that they are similar but not identical to modern hallucinations since conscious people who "relapse" into hallucinations are not bicameral.[40]: 455 About schizophrenia, Jaynes wrote:[11]: 431-432
... whether one illness or many, is in its florid stage practically defined by certain characteristics which we have stated earlier were the salient characteristics of the bicameral mind. [...] But there are great differences as well. If there is any truth to this hypothesis, the relapse is only partial. The learnings that make up a subjective consciousness are powerful and never totally suppressed. And thus the terror and the fury, the agony and the despair. [...T]he florid schizophrenic is in an opposite world to that of the god-owned laborers of Marduk or of the idols of Ur.
Jaynes allowed that his neurological model "could be mistaken (at least in the simplified version I have presented) and the other [hypotheses] true."[40]: 456 The model attributes voices, especially in the ancient bicameral mind, to the "amalgams of admonitory experience" — such as remembered commands from parents — that were "stored" in the RH (right hemisphere).: 74, 106, 428 The RH would be activated by "decision stress" to send a communication to the LH. Jaynes argues that a linguistic "code" (i.e. a verbal command) would be "the most efficient method of getting complicated cortical processing from one side of the brain to the other."[5]: 105-106 Excitation from the RH is the critical factor, and the most likely short route for a RH message to be transferred to the LH (which holds Wernicke's area) is through the anterior commissure because that is a direct physical connection between the RH and LH temporal lobes.: 103–104 [v]
Jaynes proposed two variants of his neurological model. The "stronger" variation, supposedly easier to test, is that 'voices' are generated entirely in the RH to be 'heard' in Wernicke's (LH) area. The weaker (and vaguer) model would still have excitation originate in the RH, but the "articulatory qualities of the hallucination" would somehow involve the normal LH location for speech-production, i.e. Broca's area.: 105–106
Evolutionary speculations
[edit]Language: Jaynes outlined his own theory of language evolution to account for language in both hemispheres and to focus on the social functions of vocabulary. The earliest humans, with little or no language, lived in very small groups which must have been organized to manage their strict social hierarchies, like those of other primates, using mostly "postural or visual signals" in accordance with the principles governing primate sociality.[44]: 126–131 Vocabulary may have grown through a series of stages, from vocal signals, to modifiers, then to nouns, and then to the invention of names perhaps around 10,000 BCE. Names enabled the management of individuals within larger, settled populations. The evolution of names was a necessary step towards the hallucinatory function, which was a side-effect of language comprehension.: 134
For preconscious humans — they could not tell themselves what to do — the ability to 'hear' the leader when the leader was absent, and to identify the 'voice' with the leader's name, would have provided evolutionary advantages.: 126–127 Bicameral voice-hearing would have enhanced the cohesion of a small group and reinforced the mechanisms of social control over larger populations, enabling individuals to persist at the long-term tasks which were essential for the transition from prehistoric hunter-gatherer societies to agricultural economies.
Brain plasticity: Jaynes also advocated for a concept of plasticity in the child's brain, based on evidence that under certain conditions "the normally preferred modes of neural organization": 124 are bypassed, and he speculated that the modern functional organization of the brain was achieved by selective pressure against bicamerality: "after a thousand years of psychological reorganization in which [...] bicamerality was discouraged when it appeared in early [childhood] development, [the right hemisphere language] areas function in a different way."[5]: 125
Section Notes
[edit]- ^ Richard Rhodes commented on this difficulty: "Man without language is easy: a superior primate. Man without consciousness is hard to compass."[86]
Owen Barfield also: "The consciousness of 'myself' and the distinction between 'my–self' and all other selves, the antithesis between 'myself', the observer, and the external world, the observed, is such an obvious and early fact of experience to every one of us, such a fundamental starting point of our life as conscious beings, that it really requires a sort of training of the imagination to be able to conceive of any different kind of consciousness. Yet we can see from the history of our words that this form of experience, far from being eternal, is quite a recent achievement of the human spirit [. . .] that seems to have first dawned faintly on Europe at about the time of the Reformation".[87] - ^ In a 1986 lecture, Jaynes asked: "But what then is consciousness, since I regard it as an irreducible fact that my introspections, retrospections, and imaginations do indeed exist?"[4]: 6
- ^ Jaynes extensively discusses what consciousness "is not", and why it is distinct from the cognitive processes that occur without it.[36] Similar statements about 'non-conscious' processes include: Gigerenzer (2007) "...much of our mental life is unconscious, based on processes alien to logic: gut feelings, or intuitions[, ...] on rules of thumb, and on evolved capacities";[88]: 3–4 and Kahneman (2011) "You believe you know what goes on in your mind, [but m]ost impressions and thoughts arise in your conscious experience without your knowing how they got there."[89]: 4 Oakley & Halligan (2017) and Rowe (2016) explicitly distinguish between consciousness and "executive functions" of the brain.[90][43]
- ^ Compare Kahneman, 2011: "When we think of ourselves, we identify with System 2, the conscious, reasoning self that has beliefs, makes choices, and decides what to think about and what to do [and] believes itself to be where the action is, [... whereas ...] System 1 runs automatically and System 2 is normally in a comfortable low-effort mode, in which only a fraction of its capacity is engaged."[89]: 21–24
- ^ In light of the definitional ambiguities around the term "consciousness", one of Jaynes's students, Brian McVeigh, has suggested that the term "interiority" better signified Jaynes's meaning.[91]: 42
- ^ Jaynes's 1976 analysis elaborates the following specific features of consciousness: spatialization, narratization, excerption, the analog ‘I’, the metaphor ‘me’, and conciliation. In the Afterword of the 1990 edition, he added concentration and suppression. All are causally dependent on linguistic metaphors or analogies of behavioral processes.[42] The list is not meant to be exhaustive or universal.[2]: 450-451
- ^ In the Afterword of his 1990 edition Jaynes wrote: "The basic connotative definition of consciousness is thus an analog 'I' narratizing in a functional mind-space. The denotative definition is [...] what is introspectable."[40]: 450
- ^ In an earlier work on ancient Greek language and philosophy, Bruno Snell recognized the significance of physical descriptions of the 'mind', writing: "We cannot speak about the mind or the intellect at all without falling back on metaphor."[92]
- ^ In his book, Jaynes asserts: "Understanding a thing is to arrive at a metaphor for that thing by substituting something more familiar to us. And the feeling of familiarity is the feeling of understanding."[42]: 52
- ^ Later research refers to this process as the development of theory of mind as part of the development of consciousness in children.[43]
- ^ Consciousness is "a cultural introduction, learned on the basis of language and taught to others, rather than any biological necessity."[46]: 220
- ^ Compare the transitions from 1st millennium usage of Hebrew nephesh and ruah with Greek psyche and pneuma, Latin anima and English spirit and soul in the Bible.
- ^ Jaynes mentions "Snell's parallel work on Homeric language" in a footnote on page 71.
- ^ Jaynes finds a "key to understanding" the eventual development of Greek consciousness in the history of the listed "mindlike terms in the Iliad".: 257 He refers to those terms as the "preconscious hypostases", meaning those things which, being "caused to stand under something", become "the assumed causes of action when other causes are no longer apparent."[48]: 259
- ^ Bruno Snell, in 1948, asserted the seriousness of Greek belief: "...[the Greeks] looked upon their gods as so natural and self-evident that they could not even conceive of other nations acknowledging a different faith or other gods. [...] The existence and the power of the gods are no less certain than the reality of laughter and tears..." And the earliest evidence of Greek 'atheism' appears only near the end of the 5th century BCE.[98]
- ^ This is the point in Jaynes’s book where the term is first mentioned.[64]: 75
- ^ "Language is considered to be one of the most lateralized human brain functions. Left hemisphere dominance for language has been consistently confirmed in clinical and experimental settings and constitutes one of the main axioms of neurology and neuroscience. However, [recent] functional neuroimaging studies are finding that the right hemisphere also plays a role in diverse language functions."[15]
- ^ Jaynes pointedly emphasizes that the term is misleading: "The so-called split-brain operation (which it is not — the deeper parts of the brain are still connected)...": 113
- ^ As recently as 2015, "...systematic empirical research on the phenomenology of auditory hallucinations remains scarce."[99]
- ^ The first chapters of Jaynes's book explain that consciousness is not a constant or continuous thing, though it seems so to itself.
- ^ Robert Ornstein's compilation from 1973, "The Nature of Human Consciousness: a book of readings", had leading-edge articles on the hemispheres by Michael Gazzaniga, Joseph Bogen and others.[103]
- ^ In a footnote Jaynes explicitly acknowledged that the anterior commissure had other known functions besides the bicameral.: 105
Bicameral interpretations of ancient facts
[edit]Early bicamerality
[edit]The bicameral hypothesis permits an interpretation of archeological and historical facts that accounts for the general pattern, says Jaynes, of "social organization [...] wherever and whenever civilization first began"[7]: 149 and specifically "the entire pattern of the evidence [of] the dead as gods in different regions of the world".[7]: 165 The hypothesis connects seemingly disconnected facts[a] and explains apparent mysteries.[8]: 273 For example, on the subject of the "Corpse/Personator Ceremony" in early China, Michael Carr wrote:[105]
There are already various non-bicameral explanations for […] all […] Chinese death beliefs and customs. However, without the bicameral hypothesis, at least one explanation has to be proposed for each of them. Proposing many different reasons for corresponding traditions across cultures ignores what Jaynes calls "the entire pattern of the evidence."
There are "several outstanding archeological features of ancient civilizations which can only be understood", says Jaynes,[12]: 150 according to the bicameral hypothesis. They include the burial of "the important dead as if they still lived";: 161 the ubiquitous use of idols, statuary and figurines; the monumental architecture, especially of 'god-houses' (i.e. temples) "in which no one lived, no grain was stored, and no animals were housed".[57]: 64 Jaynes presents evidence from ancient Sumeria, Ancient Egypt, Ancient Jericho, the Hittites, the Olmec, Maya, and the Inca.[57]: 62 [b]
The living dead. The hallucinated 'voice' of a group leader would still be 'heard' after the leader's death, and so the leader could seem, at least for a time, as still giving commands.[6]: 138-143 [106] Such an experience can explain the origin, as early as 9000 BCE,[57]: 55 of certain ceremonial treatments of the dead as still living.[57]: 66–67 One was burial beneath the home (as at Tel Jericho) or at the dwelling entrance (as at the "Pre-Pottery Neolithic B site of Tel Halula").[57]: 62 Another was the practice by Paleolithic skull cults of severing the head from a corpse and preserving the skull (as at Göbekli Tepe).[107] In many places there was a "double burial of the same corpse", perhaps because the 'voices' had stopped being heard.: 141 : 151 Elaborate mummification rituals, practised for thousands of years and in widely separated parts of the world, were aimed at preserving a physical body, perhaps to satisfy the 'afterlife' demands of a still-heard voice. In later millennia, texts refer to the dead persisting as "ghosts" if not "as gods".[57]: 66–67
The Natufian example
The "best defined and most fully studied Mesolithic culture [is] the Natufian[,]" located at Eynan in present-day Israel.: 138 By 9000 BCE they had a population of 200-300 persons living a settled life with primitive agriculture. It was a group too large to be manageable merely by signals and simple commands. They may have been a bicameral community. Natufians practiced ceremonial burials. The dead Natufian king appears to have been propped up in his elaborate tomb-dwelling — "the first such ever found (so far)" — as if he were still alive, as if...
...in the hallucinations of his people still giving forth his commands, [... which] was a paradigm of what was to happen in the next eight millennia. The king dead is a living god. The king’s tomb is the god’s house, the beginning of the elaborate god-house or temples[.][6]: 143
Statuary. A prominent feature of nearly all early settlements was a place of some kind for cultic statuary. It was not uncommon for a shrine to be located in a personal dwelling (e.g. 7th-6th millennium Çatal Hüyük). Some of the most common and oldest artifacts are strangely formed figurines, statues and cultic images, and thousands of them are small enough to hold in the hand. Many such figurines may have served as hallucinogenic devices: 152, 243 that stimulated the 'hearing' of bicameral voices.[6][7]
Monumental god-houses. The burial mounds found around the world were pre-cursors, in many places, of "tremendous architectural investment"[108] in the construction of complex tombs such as the ancient pyramid. Many such tombs for the 'living dead' served as the center of communal life where the "god-king's" presence was long-lasting, if not eternal. The first temples were possibly based on the function of a king's tomb as a "god-house". Alternatively, many large settlements and cities, for example 7th millennium Tel Jericho, or the later ziggurats of Ur,: 151–153 had a centrally located temple that housed a 'speaking' statue-god or life-sized effigy who could rule for multiple generations and in many places at once.: 144 Such was probably the case in Mesopotamia, where the cultic statues were maintained for generations by a dead king's successors acting as a servant priest of the statue-god.: 143 [7]: 150-164
Theocratic kingdoms
[edit]Of the great cultures of pre-classical antiquity, ancient Mesopotamia and ancient Egypt are the two most studied and best understood. Their extensive written records from before the Bronze Age collapse have been very successfully translated. The two cultures were quite different from ours today, and from each other as well, but what they had in common was a rigid social hierarchy that functioned for millennia and that bound politics and religion tightly together. They were each, in fact, a theocracy dominated by ’gods’ in an elaborate polytheistic system with a correspondingly elaborate priesthood. The two systems were typical of two types of ancient kingdoms, which probably began out of similarly primitive bicameral origins but developed differently:
- the "steward-king theocracy [… of the] Mesopotamian bicameral city-states" appeared in some variety as "the most important and widespread form of theocracy [... in] Mycenae[, ...] and, so far as we know, in India, China, and probably Mesoamerica";[93]: 178-185
- the "god-king theocracy in which the king himself is a god" [is the "more archaic": 186 system that] "existed in Egypt and at least some of the kingdoms of the Andes, and probably the earliest kingdom of Japan."[93]: 178,186
Mesopotamia
[edit]The basic facts of Ancient Mesopotamian religion (or Sumerian religion) are fairly well-established from the archaeology and texts of the Sumerians and Akkadians. Shrines and statues of gods, mostly made of wood, were everywhere, and they were central to daily life.[93]: 178–179
Throughout Mesopotamia, from the earliest times of Sumer and Akkad, all lands were owned by gods and men were their slaves. Of this the cuneiform texts leave no doubt whatsoever. Each city-state had its own principal god, and the king [was] "the tenant farmer of the god."
The god himself was a statue. The statue was not of a god (as we would say) but the god himself. […] The gods, according to cuneiform texts, liked eating and drinking, music and dancing; they required beds to sleep in and for enjoying sex with other god-statues on connubial visits from time to time; they had to be washed and dressed, and appeased with pleasant odors; they had to be taken out for drives on state occasions; and all these things were done with increasing ceremony and ritual as time went on.
Jaynes asks:[93]: 180-184
How is all this possible, continuing as it did in some form for thousands of years as the central focus of life [...if not because of bicamerality?] Everywhere in these texts it is the speech of gods who decide what is to be done. […The] rulers [are] the hallucinated voices of the gods Kadi, Ningirsu and Enlil. [...And] statues underwent mis-pi which means mouth-washing, and the ritual of pit-pi or "opening of the mouth." [...] Each individual, king or serf, had his own personal god [and] lived in the shadow of his personal god, his ili [who was responsible for every action.]
Egypt
[edit]Many basic facts of ancient Egyptian religion are similarly well-established, based on the successful decipherment of Egyptian texts in hieratic and hieroglyphics (meaning the "writing of the gods"). Egyptian beliefs and concepts are often stated in concrete terms, and Jaynes stresses that such straight-forward texts are often mis-interpreted and mis-translated to suit modern ways of thinking and philosophizing. For example, Jaynes refers to the creator god Ptah written about in the Memphite Theology, and comments:[93]: 186
. . . that the various gods are variations of Ptah’s voice or "tongue."
Now when "tongue" here is translated as something like the "objectified conceptions of his mind," as it so often is, this is surely an imposing of modern categories upon the texts.
Concerning the central mythology of the pharaohnic god-kings, "that each king at death becomes Osiris, just as each king in life is Horus[,]" Jaynes asserts:[93]: 187
Osiris [...] was not a "dying god," not "life caught in the spell of death," or "a dead god," as modern interpreters have said. He was the hallucinated voice of a dead king whose admonitions could still […] be heard, [therefore] there is no paradox in the fact that the body from which the voice once came should be mummified, with all the equipment of the tomb providing life's necessities: food, drink, slaves, women, the lot. There was no mysterious power that emanated from him; simply his remembered voice which appeared in hallucination to those who had known him and which could admonish or suggest even as it had before he stopped moving and breathing.
…and the process repeated from generation to generation.
The ka and ba
[edit]Jaynes agrees with mainstream scholarship that an important but confusing "fundamental notion": 189 in Ancient Egyptian religion is that of the ka. Jaynes observes:[93]: 190
. . . this particularly disturbing concept, which we find constantly in Egyptian inscriptions, [has been translated] in a litter of ways, as spirit, ghost, double, vital force, nature, luck, destiny, and what have you.
Texts about the ka are numerous and confusing. "Every person has his ka[. ...] Yet when one dies, one goes to one's ka.": 191 The Pharaoh and his ka, usually depicted as twins, are formed together at birth. Some texts, however, "casually say that the king has fourteen ka's!": 193 Bicamerally interpreted, the ka is "what the ili or personal god was in Mesopotamia.": 190 Pharaoh heard his ka while alive, while others would hear their own ka and would also hallucinate the Pharoah’s voice as the Pharaoh's ka, which could still be heard for some time after Pharaoh’s death.: 189–191
A related concept is that of the ba, which was usually depicted as a small humanoid bird associated with a corpse or statue of a person. The "famous Papyrus Berlin 3024, which dates about 1900 B.C." and records the "Dispute of a man with his Ba", has never been translated "at face value, as a dialogue with an auditory hallucination, much like that of a contemporary schizophrenic.": 193–194
Systemic social breakdown
[edit]Bicameral societies changed slowly over the millennia, but some changes, for example inter-cultural contact and trade, periods of expansive population growth, and natural calamities probably weakened the effectiveness of social control by the hallucinated divine beings.[46]: 206-217 While inherent instabilities made many bicameral theocratic kingdoms susceptible to collapse,: 207 only in the later millennia, after recurring breakdowns of bicameral authority, did the adaptive behavioral response of consciousness become possible; it eventually did occur, probably at different times and places.[46]: 216-222
Effects of writing
[edit]Human language and 'voices' evolved in connection to an auditory system in which the ears, unlike the eyes, cannot be closed; the hearing of sounds cannot be 'shut out'. The invention of writing, which relied on a visual system, connected language to a visual sign in a fixed location that could be looked at or avoided. Thus the use of writing was one factor that contributed to the eventual decline of the "authority of sound",: 94–97 and so of bicamerality. Originally, however, visual symbols were probably written on behalf of, and read by, the 'gods' of the right hemisphere, and the person looking at the text perhaps got the message more as "a matter of hearing […], that is, hallucinating the speech from looking at [written] picture-symbols[.]"[93]: 182
In Mesopotamia, the use of writing to encode 'divine law' (that is, the "judgement-giving") that was told to Hammurabi by his god (either Marduk or Shamash) probably enhanced the social order, at least at first.: 198–199 The practice of recording god-commanded events possibly helped the gods (i.e. the right hemisphere) remember and learn from their own past. The constant recitations and repetitions of such texts possibly produced culturally-defining epic poetry as a bicameral process. In the 1st millenium BCE, however, while the ancient texts remained as cultural artifacts, the bicameral recitation process eventually gave way to something different, supporting a major characteristic of consciousness, namely the individual's "ability to narratize memories into patterns[.]"[46]: 217-218
Loss of social order
[edit]"The smooth working of a bicameral kingdom has to rest on its authoritarian hierarchy.": 207 The admonitory functions of hallucination could respond to familiar and non-threatening situations, but might fail in unfamiliar or unmanageable situations. The success of civilized life increased the numbers of individuals' 'voices' that needed to be managed in order to maintain social order. Every established bicameral theocracy became polytheistic and had a hierarchy of priests to manage potential competition between the gods, i.e. the 'voices', of the pantheon. Many "such theocracies occasionally did [...] suddenly collapse without any known external cause.": 207 [c] Even the relatively stable bicameralities, such as in Egypt, never resolved polytheistic inconsistencies.[d] Over the course of many centuries, failures of hallucinatory authority required adaptation, or proved to be insurmountable:
- The psychological "authority of sound": 94–99 was gradually weakened, certainly by the mid-2nd millennium BCE, by the widespread use of written texts.: 209
- Inter-cultural contact between city-states, also as a result of growth, could either lead to trade relations or to conflict — but nothing in-between — depending on whether the gods on each side judged the other human as friend or foe. A judgement of the 'other' as hostile could easily lead to war, which certainly brought social chaos.: 205–207
- Besides war, natural catastrophes likely brought social chaos, followed either by long periods of rebuilding, or by migrations and potentially hostile contacts between individuals and populations.
Substitutes for divine authority
[edit]In the event of serious social disorder, "the gods could not tell you what to do[.]": 209 They became silent, or they produced more disorder.: 208–216 During the 3rd millennium BCE ancient Mesopotamian religion began to express the first forms of prayer rituals and sacrificial offerings, probably to invoke 'voices' that did not speak automatically in the face of a difficult problem.: 223–230 [e] Before consciousness could "narratize" (i.e. to 'tell the future') about an action and its consequences, a wide variety of divination rituals and the reading of omens became common practices to help a king, priest or other inquirer decide what needed to be done.[f] Eventually, and continuing into the 1st millennium BCE, Mesopotamian religion had created a superstitious world filled with countless angels and genii — beneficial half-human, half-bird messengers to the now 'distant' gods — plus countless demons, against whom protection was sought by the widespread use of amulets and exorcisms.: 230–233
The dawn of consciousness
[edit]The limited historical record of the late Bronze Age currently offers no more than clues to the possible dawn of consciousness.[12] By the end of the 3rd millennium BCE, the city owned by "Ashur" had risen to become a trading empire, Old Assyria. It collapsed but rose anew about 1380 BCE, becoming the 2nd Assyrian Empire, a militaristic, brutal conqueror unlike any before it. The new Assyrians encountered a chaos widespread throughout the region, with migrations of many peoples perhaps fleeing natural calamities. Jaynes asserted that the recorded unprecedented cruelty of the Assyrian king Tiglath-Pileser I may have been a chaotic response to the total collapse of bicameral social order.
The very practice of cruelty as an attempt to rule by fear is, I suggest, at the brink of subjective consciousness.[46]: 214
Natural disasters "certainly accelerated" the collapse of bicamerality.: 212 Jaynes originally speculated that the major cause of collapse was a volcanic eruption:
Whenever it was, whether it was one or a series of eruptions, [the collapse of Thera] set off a huge procession of mass migrations and invasions which wrecked the Hittite and Mycenaean empires, [and] threw the world into a dark ages within which came the dawn of consciousness.: 213
By 1990, Jaynes deemphasized the volcano as an immediate cause of the "dark ages" because new evidence indicated that the Minoan eruption may have occurred, or begun, as early as 1600 BCE.[110] Even so, some historians writing after Jaynes have described the end of the millennium as the catastrophic 'Late Bronze Age collapse'. It was "a form of systems collapse [. . .that] requires a widespread internal fragility" and a "broad instability" for it to make sense, and Jaynes's theory has been described as possibly the best way to explain it.[111]
Richard Dawkins and Oliver Sacks have claimed that for Jaynes consciousness began when bicameral voices became 'internalized' as one's own.[g] Jaynes, however, does not say that hallucinated voices were 'heard' differently because of consciousness, but that consciousness became possible only after 'voices' were generally silent:[47]: 233
"[Before the breakdown of bicamerality in Mesopotamia] the gods customarily had locations...such as ziggurats or household shrines [or] celestial bodies [and] the majority of gods were earth-dwellers along with men. All this changes as we enter the first millennium B.C., when, as we are proposing, the gods' voices are no longer heard."
Early centuries of consciousness
[edit]Jaynes's interpretation of the first centuries of transition to consciousness focused primarily on the ample evidence from the ancient Middle East.[h] Later scholarship aimed at the "tracking of ancient mentalities"[40]: 468 elsewhere as well. Certain mysterious Chinese funerary practices[106] can be explained according to the bicameral hypothesis, with the later Zhou dynasty, a period "approximately the same as in Greece",[40]: 468 also interpretable as a period of transition to consciousness.[114]
Greece
[edit]In Greece, the old order, dominated by (hallucinated) gods, gave way after the so-called 'Greek Dark Age' to a society of newly-conscious humans struggling, philosophically, to understand the world and their place in it next to the gods. The era has independently been interpreted by some historians as particularly significant without any reference to the bicameral hypothesis, for example Bruno Snell argued that it was the era of the Greek "Discovery of Mind".[96] Karl Jaspers proposed that the early 1st millennium BCE was a global "axial age" of cultural advancement.[i] The widely recognized and well-documented revival of culture known as classical Greece is, for Jaynes, the outcome of a cultural transition away from bicamerality. He described it as the period "when so much of what we regard as modern psychology and personality was being formed for the first time."[40]: 468 Individuals, sometimes alone in response to social disorder, or through encountering conscious others, were beginning to learn conscious behaviors. The ability took hold and spread, quickly in some places, slowly in others, while the religious legacy of bicameral culture could adapt only gradually, and began to be seen as irrational.[12]
Hebrew Bible
[edit]Regarding the "birth pangs of our subjective consciousness[,]" Jaynes asserts of the Hebrew Bible that "[n]o other literature has recorded this absolutely important event at such length or with such fullness.": 312–313 The scriptures of Judaism combine very ancient traditions together with legends and historical events. The later books of the canon record events between the ninth and fifth centuries BCE, a chaotic period of political and religious conflict reflecting the "mental struggle that followed the breakdown of the bicameral mind."[94]: 297 Jaynes devotes a chapter of his book to relevant Biblical themes, including the divine names (the Elohim and Yahweh), the problems of inconsistent 'voices' both within and between the many prophets ("nabiim" in Hebrew), and the divination practices and ever-present idols mentioned in the texts.[94]: 293-313
The "prophetic phenomenon" has been described as "universal" across cultures, and "[p]rophets, as individuals and as groups, appear in the earliest stages of Israel's history."[22] Numerous Biblical passages discuss the "pre-classical prophets" of the ninth century BCE, traveling in groups of hundreds throughout the land, with peculiar attire, engaged in a "primary task" of "the delivery of oracles." They "were regarded with some ambivalence...respected and feared [...but could also] evoke contempt [...and] were perhaps despised."[115] Jaynes mentions several episodes from the same period that indicate the elimination of frenzied false prophets he describes as 'groups of bicameral men'.[j]
Much of the physical evidence of idols has been lost, because "King Josiah had them all destroyed in 641 B.C. (II Chronicles 34: 3-7[)]."[94]: 310 [k] Jaynes discusses six sorts of idols mentioned in the Hebrew including what he calls the "most common hallucinogenic idol", the teraphim that figure in several texts.[l] In the Book of Ezekiel, 21:21 the king of Babylon used divination and consulted with idols[m] who "could seem to speak".[94]: 309
Regarding the 'true' prophets, that they heard a 'voice' was taken for granted.[n] The falsity of others' prophecy varied: either "they prophesied by Baal" (spoke in the name of a 'false god') or "they proclaim visions of their own minds, not from the mouth of the Lord".[o]
Comparing Amos and Ecclesiastes
[edit]Of the Biblical books, the Book of Amos is the oldest of those verifiably well-dated by modern scholars. It was written during the 8th century BCE, early in the almost 300-year era of "the classical prophets",[119] at about the same time that the Iliad was first written down among the Greeks.[p] The Book of Ecclesiastes dates from about 500 years later. Jaynes regards these two books as "extremes" of difference that typify comparisons between older, more bicameral, texts and newer, more conscious, texts. Jaynes comments:[94]: 296
In Amos there are no words for mind or think or feel or understand or anything similar whatever; Amos never ponders anything in his heart; he can't; he would not know what it meant. [...] he does not consciously think before he speaks; [...] He feels his bicameral voice about to speak and shushes those about him with a "Thus speaks the Lord!" and follows with an angry forceful speech which he probably does not understand himself.
Ecclesiastes is the opposite on all these points. He ponders things [deeply]. And who but a very subjective man could say, "Vanity of vanities, all is vanity," (1:2), or say that he sees that wisdom excels folly (2:13). [...] Ecclesiastes thinks, considers, is constantly comparing one thing and another, and making brilliant metaphors as he does so. Amos uses external divination, Ecclesiastes never.
Irrationality in classical antiquity
[edit]Classical texts reveal attitudes of conscious people towards phenomena that the hypothesis explains as early vestiges of lost bicamerality. For example, Socrates, famous as a rational philosopher, had his "daimonion" (personal deity).[18]: 141–164 As the culture of philosophy and rationality took hold in classical Greece and Rome, religious ecstasy was early on valued as the "divine gift" of madness,[120] while the highest poetry was the form composed "in a state of frenzy".[121]: 171 Jaynes describes a well-known passage from Plato:[11]: 405–406
In the Phaedrus, Plato calls insanity "a divine gift, and the source of the chiefest blessings granted to men."[Phaedrus, 244A] And this passage preludes one of the most beautiful and soaring passages in all the Dialogues in which four types of insanity are distinguished: prophetic madness due to Apollo, ritual madness due to Dionysus, the poetic madness "of those who are possessed by the Muses, which taking hold of the delicate and virgin soul, and there inspiring frenzy, awaken lyrical and all other numbers," and, finally, erotic madness due to Eros and Aphrodite.
According to Abraham Heschel, the prophets ("nabiim") of the Hebrew Bible have been analyzed by numerous modern scholars as having a psychology of "frenzy" and "ecstasy", if not "psychosis",[122] while the rabbis of the Talmud in the post-Biblical era viewed all claims of prophecy with suspicion and held that "the absence of ecstasy is the mark that distinguished the Hebrew prophets from all other prophets."[123] Heschel explains:[123]
The rabbis looked with irony upon the phenomena of wild ecstasy which were common in Palestine and Syria in the third century C.E. [... as stated] in the sayings of Rabbi Yohanan (d. C.E. 279), who was the head of the leading academy in Tiberias, Palestine: "From the day of the destruction of the Temple prophetic inspiration was taken away from the prophets and given to children and madmen."
The bicameral hypothesis interprets the "famous nabiim", the 'true' prophets who always knew what their 'voices' said, as "men who can be partly subjective and yet still hear the bicameral voice.": 311 They differed from the ecstatics, who displayed "a complete domination of the person and his speech by the god-side, a domination which speaks through the person but does not allow him to remember what has happened afterwards. This [vestigial] phenomenon is known as possession."[52]: 339
A similar account applies to the sibyls.: 331 According to Jaynes's historical analysis[50]: 329-332 the Greek "Age of Oracles" went through six stages as society transitioned from bicamerality to consciousness.[8] Their original simple function, to inspire 'voices', degenerated into their later ecstatic and erratic forms, sometimes with outright fakery.: 329–332 Nevertheless, pagan "oracles were the central method of making important decisions for over a thousand years after the breakdown of the bicameral mind",[50]: 321 but as they approached their eventual disappearance during the 4th century CE, they increasingly became targets of mockery by the growing community of conscious people.[16]: 331-338 [8]
Section Notes
[edit]- ^ See Michael Carr, 2006. "[Jaynes’s] hypothesis can explain many historical aspects of early civilizations."[104]
- ^ For Jaynes's review of evidence from around the world, see Origin... Bk. II, Ch. 1: Gods, Graves and Idols, pp.149-175.
- ^ Without consciousness, ancient people could not imagine a future different from the past, and so could not plan for the 'unforeseeable'. They could do no more than make use of past knowledge, which was simply the accumulation of memory and god-ordained tradition. The 'gods' were only as reliable as their knowledge and memory allowed.
- ^ In Egypt there were numerous major and minor cults, of Re, Ptah, Min, Osiris, Horus, and Set, etc. "Efforts to rationalize the theologies were taking place, but the inconsistencies...were never to be satisfactorily removed."[109]
- ^ In Origin... Bk. II, Ch. 4: A Change of Mind in Mesopotamia, pp. 223-254.
- ^ Jaynes discusses four kinds of Mesopotamian practices as substitutes for lost bicameral functions: omens and omens in texts and dreams, sortilege, augury, and spontaneous divination. All of these relied heavily on metaphorical thinking, and served as precursors of the eventual development of consciousness.: 236–246
- ^ Dawkins wrote: for Jaynes, consciousness began "the moment in history when it dawned on people that the external voices that they seemed to be hearing were really internal."[112] Sacks wrote: "Jaynes proposed, with the rise of modern consciousness, the voices became internalized and recognized as our own."[113]
- ^ Jaynes presents his comparative evidence in separate chapters on Mesopotamia, Egypt, Greece and the Hebrew Bible.[12]
- ^ Bruno Snell’s work is acknowledged by Jaynes in the 1976 edition in a footnote on page 71. The 'axial age' is noted in his 1990 edition on page 468.
- ^ Jaynes references verses I Kings 18:4, I Kings 18:40, and I Kings 22:10.[94]: 311
- ^ The inserted right-parenthesis is missing in the original from Jaynes, page 310.
- ^ The idols Jaynes discusses are: elil (in Book of Isaiah); a "matstsebah for anything set up on a pillar or altar"; "the tselem, a cast or molten statue"; a "carved statue or pesel"; the "sun idols of unknown shape called chammanim"; and the "most common hallucinogenic idol was the terap".: 308–309
- ^ "For the king of Babylon has halted at the fork where these two roads diverge, to take the omens. He has shaken the arrows, questioned the teraphim, inspected the liver."[116]
- ^ Heschel discusses the work of scholars whose "scientific inquiry" rejects any supernatural explanation of ancient prophecy, yet they accept that "[when] the prophets lived, the belief was common that the deities revealed themselves to men."[117]
- ^ Quotations are from Heschel (1962) referencing Jeremiah 23:13-16.[118] The King James Version of the Bible reads: "...they speak a vision of their own heart, and not out of the mouth of the LORD." This precisely translates the original Hebrew word "heart" without converting it to "mind". The common equivalence of 'heart' and 'mind' is just one example consistent with Jaynes's argument that the 'location of consciousness' is not necessarily or obviously 'the brain', but can be situated almost anywhere we imagine it to be.[36]: 46
- ^ Modern scholarship approximates that the oldest recorded Upanishads in India were perhaps from about this time, but for Jaynes neither the "bicameral Veda" nor the "ultra subjective Upanishads" can be verifiably dated "as authentic to their times.": 313 He notes, nevertheless, that "[i]n India, the oldest literature is the Veda, which were dictated by gods to the rishi or prophets" notably as right-hemisphere poetry.: 362
Vestiges of bicamerality in the modern world
[edit]Many phenomena, some familiar and some strange, display varying degrees of "diminished consciousness": 324 or trance. Jaynes argued that such possible "vestiges" of ancient bicamerality are highly dependent on social processes, may possibly involve significant differences in how the cerebral hemispheres interact, with probably significant right hemisphere processing.[16] Jaynes's book included chapters on the following key examples: hypnosis, which is highly dependent on 'outside' authority;[53] a comparison of prophetic voice-hearing and spiritual possession (possible right hemisphere takeover of normally left hemisphere functions);[52] some psychological aspects of music, poetry and song, which all have ancient roots and links to religion.[51] Jaynes also proposed a bicameral historical theory of oracles and sibyls,[50] and argued that the hallucinations of severe schizophrenia[11] might be a "partial relapse": 405 to bicamerality where the subjective consciousness of the "modern schizophrenic struggles against the more primitive mental organization...in which the hallucination ought to do the controlling.": 432
General bicameral paradigm
[edit]The general bicameral paradigm is a hypothetical social-neurological process proposed by Jaynes to explain certain phenomena (e.g. hypnosis, spirit possession) as vestiges of ancient bicamerality because the bicameral-like functions of the brain might become activated or even dominant. In general, the result is a trance state of diminished consciousness,: 325 where the Self, the individuality of consciousness, is displaced or replaced by dependence on a 'higher authority' (e.g. hypnotist, demagogue, demon, or voice).[16] The process is culturally variable. Jaynes listed four aspects of the paradigm:[50]: 324
- the collective cognitive imperative, or belief system, a culturally agreed-on expectancy or prescription which defines the particular form of a phenomenon and the roles to be acted out within that form;
- an induction or formally ritualized procedure whose function is the narrowing of consciousness by focusing attention on a small range of preoccupations;
- the trance itself, a response to both the preceding, characterized by a lessening of consciousness or its loss, the diminishing of the analog 'I,' or its loss, resulting in a role that is accepted, tolerated, or encouraged by the group; and
- the archaic authorization to which the trance is directed or related to, usually a god, but sometimes a person who is accepted by the individual and his culture as an authority over the individual, and who by the collective cognitive imperative is prescribed to be responsible for controlling the trance state.
In the modern world, some cultures treat voice-hearing positively, making room for both voices and normal consciousness, while others negatively treat voices as a disruption.[81]
Section Notes
[edit]Criticisms and rejoinders
[edit]Jaynes is quoted in 1978 describing the wide range of academic responses to his book as “from people who feel [the ideas are] very important all the way to very strong hostility.”[49]: 72 Academic debate over Jaynes’s ideas has focused mostly on his notions of consciousness and only indirectly on the bicameral hypothesis. One of the early and persistent critics was philosopher Ned Block who responded harshly to Jaynes’s speculative approach and “preposterous” conclusions. In a short book review in 1977, Block dismissed the notion of a non-conscious mentality as “absurd”. He described Jaynes's book as “strange, fascinating” but “never boring”, containing “many confusions”, “crackpot” and “implausible”.[28] Block’s critique has been described as reflecting “an issue many scientists remain sympathetic to — how could anyone think consciousness is a cultural construction?”[10]: 171 In 2021, however, philosopher Susan Blackmore described Jaynes's description of the problem of consciousness as one of the best.[80]
In 2006, biographers Woodward and Tower reported that Jaynes "felt he had not truly succeeded" in his lifelong work because, in their words, "He was right" about his feeling that "there were people who disagreed with him [who] had not really read his book or understood it."[124] Psycholinguist John Limber concurred, writing "When OC was published, critics had a field day — everyone could find a topic or conjecture that they disagreed with… [Jaynes's ideas were] intriguing, imaginative, preposterous, crazy… In retrospect, most of these critics — myself included — just ignored Jaynes's early chapters [about] what consciousness is not."[125]
In 2016, Marcel Kuijsten argued that Jaynes’s theorizing "continues to be ahead of much of the current thinking in consciousness studies"[17][a] and that "the vast majority of critiques of the theory are based on misconceptions about what Jaynes actually said".[33]
The 'split-brain' criticism
[edit]A claim has been made that the bicameral mind was some sort of 'split brain'.[127][b] The same point has been made as a criticism, that "Jaynes' bicameral model requires"[78]: 12 that the human brain was split at the time the Iliad was written[128]: 4 [129]: 2.2 and that, for consciousness to have arisen, "Jaynes believed that the development of nerve fibres connecting the two hemispheres gradually integrated brain function",[128]: 4 leading to a conclusion that "Jaynes's thesis does not stand up to" the fact that there were no recent "radical structural changes in the brain."[128]: 5
This criticism is contradicted by a claim from the Julian Jaynes Society website: "The transition from bicamerality to consciousness was largely a cultural change, not an evolutionary one." [original italics][129]: 2.2 In Jaynes's book, a chapter titled 'The Double Brain': 100–125 presented discoveries and speculations about the cerebral hemispheres differing functionally, at no time suggesting either that they had ever been physically 'disconnected' or that their functions had been 'integrated' by evolution.[129]: 2.2 Jaynes wrote about "the brain's plasticity" in reference to "psychological capacities": 122 and "psychological reorganization",[5]: 125 not in reference to "brain architecture"[78]: 12 as some critics have stated. Jaynes and his supporters fully agree with the scientific consensus against an ancient physiological disconnection between the two hemispheres:[45]
"According to Jaynes, there is no substantial difference between our brains today and those of bicameral people 3,000 years ago."[130]
The 'use-mention' debate
[edit]Philosopher Ned Block argued that Jaynes had confused the "nature of people's thought processes with the nature of their theories of their thought processes."[28] In other words, according to Block, ancient humans could 'use' consciousness but did not 'mention' it in their texts only because they had not developed the concept of consciousness, yet they, like us, were "surely" conscious because "it is a basic biological feature of us" and also "...it is obvious that [consciousness] is not a cultural construction."[c] In Block's view, Jaynes's ancient evidence does not show the absence of consciousness, only that "the concept of consciousness arrived around late in the 2nd millennium B.C."[30]: 310
Daniel Dennett (who, like Jaynes, held that consciousness is a cultural construction[30]: 313 ) countered that there are things, such as money, baseball, and consciousness, that cannot exist without the concept of the thing.[27] Jaynes acknowledged Dennett's argument, adding that "...there are many instances of mention and use being identical." The concepts, e.g. of money, or law, or good and evil, are the same as the thing. Rather than 'confusing' the concept of consciousness with the use of it, Jaynes replied, "we are fusing them [because] they are the same."[40]: 454
About 'consciousness'
[edit]Some have been quick to reject Jaynes's arguments based on their own, often vague, preconceptions rather than his detailed discussion of the problem of consciousness,[33] and his early chapters about "what consciousness is not.”[125]
Consciousness is not 'perception' or 'cognition'
In 1990 Jaynes acknowledged that his whole argument was "contradictory to the usual and . . . superficial views of consciousness," and he reiterated that "the most common error" people make "is to confuse consciousness with perception."[40]: 447-449
But there can be no progress in the science of consciousness until careful distinctions have been made between what is introspectable and all the hosts of other neural abilities we have come to call cognition. Consciousness is not the same as cognition and should be sharply distinguished from it.[40]: 447
Consciousness is not 'the Self'
The 'Self' is something put together by language as a product of consciousness over a lifetime of remembered experiences and stories, something that "we come to construct or invent, on a continuing basis, in ourselves and in others" as "the answer to the question 'Who am I?'"[40]: 457-458 [d] The Jaynesian view differs from the "classic notion of 'mind' or self" as "an individually bounded, embodied, efficient cause,"[32] a view which is to some extent expressed, on the one hand, in the neuroscience reductionism that sees consciousness as a 'neurological event', and on the other hand in the cognitive science model that sees it as a 'mental state'.[32] The 'Self' of Jaynesian consciousness is not the brain in whole or in part, nor an event in the brain, and not a state of the brain.
Consciousness is not 'volition' or 'executive control'
Whether consciousness is confused with perception or not, its role in volition or 'self-control' is often presumed.[90] In his book, Jaynes explains how it is that thinking happens before consciousness of thinking: "one does one's thinking before one knows what one is to think about." (Jaynes's italics): 39 Jaynes made a definitive statement about volition, but only about its bicameral, non-conscious form:[97]: 98-99
The explanation of volition in subjective conscious men is still a profound problem that has not reached any satisfactory solution. But in bicameral men, ... volition came as a voice that was in the nature of a neurological command, in which the command and the action were not separated, in which to hear was to obey.
The problem of volition is also related to another major feature of consciousness, namely "narratization",: 63–64 which is tied to the notion of the 'Self', while its role in volition is limited. Jaynes argued that right-hemisphere "narratization in epics" was first based on writing, and was how the bicameral 'gods' organized memory of their own "god-commanded events".: 217–219 In consciousness, however, narratization is how pieces of experience and memory become connected into large patterns that can 'make sense' of behavior or to some degree 'inform' unconscious processes but not 'control' them.: 63–64
Oakley and Halligan, the authors of a 2017 paper, affirm a distinction between consciousness and volition in their discussion of the "personal narrative".[90] They describe "the non-consciously generated, self-referential psychological content of the personal narrative" as a major aspect of consciousness, and they argue that the "contents of consciousness" are products of non-conscious "executive self-control" systems that operate outside "conscious experience":[90]
Despite the compelling subjective experience of executive self-control, we argue that “consciousness” contains no top-down control processes and that "consciousness" involves no executive, causal, or controlling relationship with any of the familiar psychological processes conventionally attributed to it.
What consciousness is...
For Jaynes, the problem of understanding consciousness had always been one of finding a good metaphor for consciousness, that is, finding something that consciousness is like. The difficulty is that there is nothing in the 'outside world' that is like consciousness. Jaynes "sketched out" his "somewhat rough-hewn beginning": 66 of the complex linguistic basis of consciousness and its various features, and he summarized as follows:[42]: 55
Subjective conscious mind is an analog of what is called the real world. It is built up with a vocabulary or lexical field whose terms are all metaphors or analogs of behavior in the physical world. Its reality is of the same order as mathematics. It allows us to shortcut behavioral processes and arrive at more adequate decisions. Like mathematics, it is an operator rather than a thing or repository. And it is intimately bound up with volition and decision.
Elsewhere: "Conscious mind is a spatial analog of the world and mental acts are analogs of bodily acts. Consciousness operates only on objectively observable things. ... there is nothing in consciousness that is not an analog of something that was in behavior first. ... consciousness is [the] invention of an analog world on the basis of language, paralleling the behavioral world even as the world of mathematics parallels the world of quantities of things[.]"[42]: 66
Ancient mirrors and the 'mirror test'
[edit]In 1990, Jaynes discussed and rejected certain claims that the mirror test is evidence of self-awareness in animals.[40]: 457-460 The 'Self' which is constructed in Jaynesian consciousness is not the body or the face: what a person or an animal sees in a mirror is not the 'Self'.
Self-awareness usually means the consciousness of our own persona over time, a sense of who we are, our hopes and fears, as we daydream about ourselves in relation to others. We do not see our conscious selves in mirrors, even though that image may become the emblem of the self in many cases. [...] The animal [looking in a mirror] is not shown to be imagining himself anywhere else, or thinking of his life over time, or introspecting in any sense — all signs of a conscious self.[40]: 460
Jaynes doubts that the use of mirrors in antiquity is evidence of ancient consciousness, and he alludes to research, new at the time, examining the "mystery" of Mayan mirrors that were possibly used for divination.[40]: 458n. [132]
On 'zombies' and other 'fringe minds'
[edit]Since the 1990's, much philosophical discussion about consciousness has inconclusively revolved around the notion of the "philosophical zombie" — an imaginary entity human-like in all respects except that it lacks 'consciousness' or 'experience' of some sort[e] which the philosophers variously refer to with terms like "subjective character of experience" or "qualia" or "phenomenal consciousness". These terms and concepts, which Peter M. Hacker has sharply critiqued,[f] are largely unconnected to Jaynes's arguments. Even so, some philosophers have rejected the possibility of bicamerality because it seems 'zombie-like' "based on their definition of consciousness, not Jaynes's." (author's italics)[134] Bicameral humans were not 'philosophical zombies':[g]
While the ancients surely were aware and had perceptual experiences like ours, is it possible they did not have the interior dialogue that Jaynes refers to? Like other readers, I had projected my own pre-existing notion of consciousness onto OC, neglecting Jaynes's own words...[135]
Bicameral man was intelligent, had language, was highly social, and could think and problem-solve; only these processes took place in the absence of an introspectable internal mind-space.[136]
Jan Sleutels[30] and Gary Williams[79] have attempted to clarify the differences between, on the one hand, the 'concepts' and 'thoughts' usually associated with conventional notions of consciousness, and on the other hand, the less familiar 'nonconscious concepts' necessary to make sense of bicamerality and Jaynesian consciousness. Sleutels discusses how the problematic nature of bicameral humans (i.e."Greek zombies") is precisely a problem of how to understand the "fringe minds" of creatures such as "infants, early hominids, animals" that cannot speak about their 'minds'.[30]: 306–307 Williams has argued for "three forms of mentality (reactive, bicameral, J-conscious)"[79]: 227 as a way to reconcile the philosophers' terminology within a Jaynesian framework.
Bicamerality is "secular theology"
[edit]Sociologist W. T. Jones, whose primary interest was the "sociology of belief", asked in 1979 "Why, despite its implausibility, is [Jaynes's] book taken seriously by thoughtful and intelligent people?"[29]: 1 Jones conceded — in agreement with Jaynes — "that the language in which talk about consciousness is conducted is metaphorical" but he flatly contradicted the idea, as Jones put it, "that consciousness 'is' metaphorical or that it has been 'created' by metaphor"; rather, in Jones's view, a metaphor is simply a "verbal token . . . that 'stands for' [an] experienced similarity[.]"[29]: 3–5 Jones also argued that Jaynes was "biased" with respect to three "cosmological orientations":[29]: 18–21 1) that Jaynes showed "hostility to Darwin" and to gradualist natural selection; 2) that Jaynes had both "a bias against consciousness" and a "longing for 'lost bicamerality'" and believed (says Jones) that "we would all be better off if 'everyone' were once again schizophrenic"; 3) that Jaynes had a "desire for a sweeping, all-inclusive formula that explains everything that has happened[.]" Jones wrote that "those who share these biases [...] are likely to find the book convincing; those who do not will reject [Jaynes's] arguments."[29]: 21 Jones dismissed the bicameral proposition by calling it "secular theology" rather than science, and he even questioned whether Jaynes intended to be taken seriously. He described Jaynes's book as:
... not a scientific treatise at all - not scientific history nor scientific archaeology nor scientific neurophysiology. And if that is the case, then it should not be judged by the usual criterion for assessing scientific hypothesis. [. . . I]t presents a vision of the world as a whole [...] in a language that looks scientific, rather than in the language of theology. [...] My description of Mr. Jaynes’ book as secular theology [explains] the reasons for [the book’s] success, despite its lack of scientific rigor[;. . .] that it is a new gospel, a world-picture startlingly different from any we are accustomed to and one in which everything has its secure place and all is accounted for.[29]: 24–25
Jones was described, in 1993, by Laura Mooneyham-White as "one of Jaynes's most thoroughgoing critics".[62]: 181 Mooneyham-White interpreted Jones’s critique as part of a debate between the values of scientific and non-scientific ways of knowing, between "scientific and visionary discourse".[62]: 187 According to Mooneyham-White, Jones and many other scientists rejected the notion of a "radical discontinuity"[62]: 180 dividing human beings from other biological forms; therefore they rejected Jaynes’s argument that consciousness marked such a discontinuity. Jaynes apparently affirmed discontinuity when, in 1983, he said: "I am a strict behaviorist [only] up to 1000 B.C. when consciousness develops in the one species that has a syntactic language, namely, ourselves."[62]: 181 [h] Mooneyham-White commented:
This belief in discontinuity, in an absolute break between conscious human beings and other forms of life, has garnered Jaynes an inordinate amount of criticism from his fellow scientists, as one might expect.[62]: 181
She argued that the discontinuity Jaynes "tolerates" is not metaphysical, but exists "in terms of natural science alone": that the divide between bicamerality and consciousness is a consequence of "complex social relationships" and language;[62]: 182–184 that Jaynes's work is a "monumental critique" and rejection of metaphysical explanations for both religion and consciousness;[i] and that
... for Jaynes, all forms of questing after transcendence are […] equally compelling, equally misguided. The religious imperative [inherited from bicamerality] is inescapable but doomed as chimerical.[62]: 185
Jaynes, however, applies this critique not only to religion but to science as well: that the search for truth through science is a modern "quest for authorization": 317–338 and for "certainty" in the wake of lost bicamerality. Jaynes wonders aloud about what motivates science:
In this final chapter, I wish to turn to science itself and point out that it too, and even my entire essay, can be read as a response to the breakdown of the bicameral mind. For what is the nature of this blessing of certainty that science so devoutly demands in its very Jacob-like wrestling with nature? Why should we demand that the universe make itself clear to us? Why do we care?[61]: 433
Jaynes "identifies Darwinism, Marxism, Freudianism, and behaviorism"[62]: 186 as major examples of "scientisms" of the modern era:
[... those] clusters of scientific ideas which come together and almost surprise themselves into creeds of belief, scientific mythologies which fill the very felt void left by the divorce of science and religion in our time.[61]: 441
Near the end of his book Jaynes twice says of it, "this essay is no exception.": 443, 445 According to Mooneyham-White, Jones's criticism "seized upon [this admission] as crucial evidence of the unscientific nature of Jaynes’s ideas."[62]: 187 But Mooneyham-White concluded that Jones's position may have come from a rival scientism that cannot allow any discontinuities, and cannot recognize its own dependence on "the necessary relationship between any comprehensive scientific theory and [a system of] belief."[62]: 188
Section Notes
[edit]- ^ The Jaynesian approach stands apart from that of 'consciousness studies', which Peter M. Hacker has sharply critiqued without any reference to Jaynes: "[T]he contemporary philosophical conception of consciousness that is embraced by the ‘consciousness studies community' is incoherent [...]"[126]: 14–15
- ^ For example, Smith (2007), p 34:"Ancient voice-hearing, according to Jaynes, was caused by a physical split between the right and left hemispheres of the brain that only "mended" itself three thousand years ago..."
- ^ Block is quoted in Sleutels, 2006.[30]: 312, 311 Sleutels argued against the weakness of Block's intuition that consciousness must be biological: "What is most remarkable about Block's argument against the possibility of non-conscious human minds is its absence[.]"[131]
- ^ "The analog 'I' is the second most important feature of consciousness. It is not to be confused with the self, which is an object of consciousness in later development."[40]: 450
- ^ Thomas Metzinger dismisses the 'zombie' debate as no longer relevant to the consciousness studies community because its proponents covertly rely on an "ill-defined folk psychological umbrella term", namely 'consciousness':
(25:57)Sam Harris: So you’re not a fan anymore, if you ever were, of the framing by David Chalmers of the Hard Problem of Consciousness?
Th. Metzinger: No, that’s so boring. I mean, that’s last century. I mean, you know, we all respect Dave [Chalmers], and we know he is very smart and has got a very fast mind, no debate about that. But Conceivability Arguments are just very, very weak. If you have an ill-defined folk psychological umbrella term like “consciousness”, then you can pull off all kinds of scenarios and zombie thought experiments. It doesn’t really— It helped to clarify some issues in the mid 90’s, but the consciousness community has listened to this and just moved on. I mean nobody of the serious researchers in the field thinks about this anymore, but it has taken on like a folkloristic life of its own. A lot of people talk about the Hard Problem who wouldn’t be able to state what it consists in now.[133] - ^ "[...] Consciousness studies became the [sic] all the rage. Conferences proliferated, new journals were founded, a stream of articles and books on consciousness rapidly turned to a flood. A common article of faith among the self-styled ‘consciousness studies community’ is that [...] experience or ‘phenomenal consciousness’ is to be explained by reference to the fact that there is something that it is like to have it.
Once one has gone down this cul-de-sac, then a flood of apparently deep problems follow. [...] the contemporary philosophical conception of consciousness that is embraced by the ‘consciousness studies community’ is incoherent [...]"[126]: 14–15 - ^ "When Jaynes describes early civilization as being populated by people who have not yet developed consciousness, he is not implying these were civilizations of "zombies" in the popular sense of the term."[134]
- ^ Jaynes, quoted in Mooneyham (1993), was speaking at the 1983 McMaster-Bauer Symposium on Consciousness. Mooneyham-White discusses the stance against discontinuity as a possible ‘bias’ in favor of evolution and against metaphysical and spiritual explanations of human difference.[62]: 182
- ^ "…Jaynes’s quest for a materialistic answer will lead him to his monumental critique of religion, his assertion that all religious impulses are merely nostalgic vestiges of our own bicameral auditory hallucinations, the voices we called gods but which were in reality only emanating from our right hemispheres."[62]: 182–183
Research
[edit]When the hypothesis was proposed, the tools to investigate language processes in the brain were limited, and the prevailing neurological model at the time emphasized the 'dominance' of one hemisphere. One early study, in 1982, had some supportive results for Jaynes’s model.[137] A paper in the American Journal of Psychiatry in 1986 argued against it.[138] A decade later, new neuroimaging techniques were used in a study discussed in The Lancet[139] and the Journal of Psychiatry and Neuroscience in support of Jaynes’s theory.[140] As of 2020, the brain's language system is known to be more complex than it seemed in the 20th century "classical model",[a] and the right hemisphere has a known distinctive role in both linguistic and non-linguistic communication.[142] A number of competing models exist to describe and explain verbal hallucinations.[143][144][145][142] An "abnormal asymmetry" involving abnormal right hemisphere activity[146] has been linked with severe schizophrenia but more with its distress than with voices,[11][145] and the 'hearing of voices' is not necessarily a disorder or disease.[19] The simple neuropsychological model proposed by Jaynes for ancient voices might not explain all the phenomena — neurological, phenomenological, cultural — of modern verbal hallucinations, and the right hemisphere's role remains controversial.[142][25]: 127
The cerebral hemispheres
[edit]The 'split-brain': one mind or two?
[edit]Since the 1960's, the study of so-called "split brains" was enabled by surgically "cutting the corpus callosum,"[b] and has been a major source of knowledge about the abilities of each hemisphere and the differences between them.[148] Much remains to be learned about how the hemispheres interact in the normally connected, healthy brain.
In a 2020 paper on split-brain research, the authors state that "the central question, whether each hemisphere supports an independent conscious agent, is not settled yet"[149] and there is still no definitive answer to "the intriguing question of how unity of consciousness is related to brain processes."[150] In this paper the problem of the 'unity of consciousness' does not distinguish between 'introspection' and sensory, especially visual, awareness. The paper asserts that, to date, more is known about visual processes than about other cognitive abilities, perhaps because of "a bias throughout cognitive neuroscience and psychology, leading to a strong focus on vision in split-brain research."[151] In addition, the prevailing view among cognitive neuroscientists is "that consciousness [visual awareness] in a split-brain is split" because of the assumption that "each cortical hemisphere houses an independent conscious agent."[152] The "currently dominant theories about conscious awareness — the Integrated Information Theory [...] and the Global Neuronal Workspace Theory [...] — may be critically dependent on the validity of this [split consciousness] view."[150]
Contrary evidence is discussed. For example: in some split-brain patients "perceptual processing is largely split, yet response selection and action control appear to be unified under certain conditions."[152] This is interpreted to indicate that some sort of inter-hemispheric communication takes place despite the 'split', so that the 'independence' of the hemispheres cannot be clearly established.
The paper suggests for future research that the "first question" to be answered towards the goal of "understanding unity of mind" is to improve understanding of RH language abilities.[149]
Hemispheric asymmetries, cerebral torque, and plasticity
[edit]Anatomical hemispheric asymmetries, which are found in many species, are thought to correlate with "lateralized specialization" of functions that provide evolutionary advantages, and in humans particularly with language and handedness. These correlations are interrelated in complex ways by genetics, neuro-chemistry, embryonic events, experience and disease.[153] Some asymmetries, or some degrees of asymmetry, may depend less on genetics than on brain plasticity in response to developmental and experiential events:[154] for example, some aspects of lateralization might be decided by fetal positioning in the womb, or fetal exposure to ultrasound.[155] While chimpanzees and humans might have some hemispheric asymmetries in common, the greater degree of asymmetry in the human brain seems generally indicative of higher human abilities such as language.[156]
One major hemispheric difference is that "the left hemisphere has a greater preference for within-hemisphere interactions, whereas the right hemisphere has interactions that are more strongly bilateral."[157]
While both sides resemble each other at the macrostructural level, they differ developmentally,[158] and the brain may mature into varied "types" of hemispheric functional organization.[159] Different cognitive processes can lateralize in different ways, accounting for "reversed asymmetries or the absence of asymmetry" as well.[160] As of 2019, functional and cognitive consequences of anatomical asymmetries require further study,[161] and research has focused on comparing variability of 'normal' and 'atypical' cerebral asymmetry.[159]
The most prominent aspect of asymmetry in the human brain, known since at least the 1980's, is the counter-clockwise twist, or "cerebral torque" which has also been called the "Yakovlevian torque".[162][156] A 2019 systematic analysis of cerebral torque concluded that it is a specifically human, genetically-defined, 3-dimensional pattern underlying "the uniqueness of asymmetries in the human brain."[163] A uniquely human evolutionary event might account for the torque and its developmental progression in the human embryo, where the RH starts with an earlier and more advanced structural growth of the "frontal-motor" parts of the cortex, and the LH follows later, with structural enhancement in the posterior parts of the LH cortex.[163] Atypical degrees of torque have been associated with atypical specialization of hemispheric functions.
Right-hemisphere language
[edit]In 2005, Mitchell and Crow interpreted the effect of cerebral torque as a challenge to the simplistic view of LH dominance for language.[142] They
...outline a bi-hemispheric theory of the neural basis of language that emphasizes the role of the sapiens-specific cerebral torque in determining the four-chambered nature of the human brain in relation to the origins of language and the symptoms of schizophrenia.[164]
In their model, not only would language functions be quite different within each hemisphere, but, because of the torque, there might be two asymmetric channels for inter-hemispheric language processing — primarily R to L across the "anterio-motor" lobes (near Broca's area), primarily L to R across the "posterio-sensory" lobes (near Wernicke's area).[165] The LH internally is primarily responsible for sensory-motor processing and primary lexicon, while the RH, with "a degree of autonomy" stores "a second part of the lexicon, comprising more remote, variable and often affectively charged associations"; processing within the RH "gives rise to distinction between meanings on the one hand [posteriorly], and thoughts and intentions on the other [anteriorly]."[166]
The "era of the classical model" of locations and LH (left hemisphere) exclusivity for language "is over."[141] The "essential" RH role in language is becoming increasingly appreciated.[c]
The right hemisphere is critical for perceiving sarcasm, integrating context required for understanding metaphor, inference, and humour, as well as recognizing and expressing affective or emotional prosody–changes in pitch, rhythm, rate, and loudness that convey emotions.[167]
In their 2005 paper, Mitchell and Crow present an extensive review of essential RH "higher order language functions" and dysfunctions, followed by their "four-chambered" neuro-psychological theory of language that emphasizes the "right hemisphere language functions [necessary] for successful social communication[.]"[164]
While exploration of RH language abilities has mostly been done in the context of recovery from lost LH abilities, studies have more recently looked at the normal RH role in language processing among healthy, conscious people,[15] as well as language deficits from RH damage.[168] Such research of normal, "essential" RH language abilities is necessary to better understand the neuropsychology of language in general, but also that of schizophrenia.
Phenomenology of 'voices'
[edit]The term auditory hallucination, which implies all kinds of 'sound-like' phenomena, is often used interchangeably with AVH (auditory verbal hallucination) which means "voices" (as in the quotations below). Voices are the most common sounds 'heard'. The experiential characteristics of verbal hallucinations have been minimally researched:
Auditory hallucinations — or voices — are a common feature of many psychiatric disorders and are also experienced by individuals with no psychiatric history. Understanding of the variation in subjective experiences of hallucination is central to psychiatry, yet systematic empirical research on the phenomenology of auditory hallucinations remains scarce.[99]
A 'voice' is not always 'auditory': sometimes, with non-verbal or "fuzzy" hallucinations "a message or meaning is communicated without being heard (soundless voices)."[169]
Most research into hallucinations has been done to learn how better to be rid of them, since most studies have been done with patients for whom the 'voices' are distressing:
Auditory hallucinations (AVH) have been described since antiquity, but have been identified as pathological only for the last 3 centuries. [...] AVH are characterized by the perception of voices without external stimuli, typically located outside of themselves by patients but also, and more and more described, from within of [sic] the subject’s head. The content of voices is frequently accompanied by a negative emotional valence and often with a lived experience described as distressing. [...] The pathophysiology underlying AVH is far from fully understood. [...] In summary, ... the temporal cortex [is] a potential target for brain stimulation to reduce AVH."[143]
Some recent studies have looked at comparisons between the AVH of psychotics and those of healthy 'hearers'.[20][21][170] Voice-hearing is often associated with negative experiences and harmful behaviour,[d] but can sometimes be personally meaningful,[172] and some cultures regard voices, whether positively or negatively, as spiritually significant.[173][81]
The variety of AVH is a matter of importance because the various "sub-types" may have different causes.[174]
Explaining verbal hallucination (AVH)
[edit]Bi-hemispheric models
[edit]An explosion of discoveries and speculations about brain laterality have taken place since Jaynes began his writing on the matter in the 1960's. In 1990, he expressed caution against "popularization" about the 'two sides of the brain' that verged on "shrill excesses" of interpretation. Still, he felt that research findings to that time were "generally in agreement with what we might expect to find in the right hemisphere on the basis of the bicameral hypothesis."[40]: 454-455
In 2005, Marcel Kuijsten (founder of the Julian Jaynes Society) reviewed research that "provides strong evidence for Jaynes's neurological model" while acknowledging that the "neurobiology of hallucinations is complex and a definitive theory has not yet emerged."[175] Kuijsten claimed in 2016: "Beginning in 1999, numerous neuroimaging studies have demonstrated a right/left temporal lobe interaction during auditory hallucinations, confirming Jaynes's neurological model."[176] The Society maintains a website with supporting research.[45]
Also in 2005, Mitchell and Crow presented their "bi-hemispheric theory of the neural basis of language" that explicitly addresses the problem of 'voices'. Their "four-quadrant concept...provides a framework for understanding the phenomena of psychosis"[165] because, in their view, "schizophrenia and language have a common [evolutionary] origin".[165] The authors refer to Jaynes and then present their model of how "auditory hallucinations [could] arise in the right hemisphere, and perhaps for that reason lack the characteristic of being self-generated."[165]
Cases of AVH with more negative experiences, such as command hallucinations, seem to be more strongly connected to "reduced leftward asymmetry", and in general, "the relative lack of asymmetry observed in schizophrenic brains" correlates with "disrupted inter-hemispheric connectivity" or with greater than normal RH activity.[177]
A paper in 2019 reported that "current literature emphasizes a concept that AVH result from abnormal activation, connectivity and integration within the auditory, language, and memory brain networks."[178] Looking at connectivity among the "interhemispheric auditory pathways" the authors built on "a steadily growing number of studies"[e] to present "converging evidence for an interhemispheric miscommunication due to [excitatory-to-inhibitory] imbalance as one correlate of AVH[.]"[179]
Unresolved issues
[edit]A study in 2010 concluded that "decreased language lateralization" (i.e. greater than normal RH language activity) is characteristic of psychotics with AVH (auditory verbal hallucinations), but the researchers could not establish that the same was true for AVH-hearers in general.[145] Just as there are sub-types of AVH experience,[174] there might be multiple mechanisms to account for them.[23][144]
As of 2014, how the corpus callosum regulates inter-hemispheric communication remains uncertain.[177]
Alternate models
[edit]LH inner speech: An alternative psychological approach to AVH emphasizes the study of normal "inner speech" — when people 'talk to themselves' — and how it can sometimes be abnormally experienced or mis-interpreted as an alien voice, i.e. as an auditory hallucination.[128] It is unclear how the 'motor' act would be converted into a 'perceptual experience'.[180]
LH speech perception error: A LH "inner hearing" (rather than 'inner speech') model has been proposed, suggesting that "auditory hallucinations generate activity in the speech regions in the left hemisphere much like real auditory input (causing a perceptual experience)."[181]
Traumatic memory: Traumatic or abusive experiences have been suggested as the source of the "strongly negative emotional component" of hallucinations, but "only about 10-20% of the 'voices' patients experience 'hearing' is about actual memories[.]"[180]
Section Notes
[edit]- ^ "...the era of the classical model is over. The underlying conceptualization of the relation between brain and language is hopelessly underspecified, both from the biological point of view as well as from the linguistic and psychological perspectives. ...local regions, processing streams, the two hemispheres, and distributed global networks are now implicated in language function in unanticipated ways."[141]: 2
- ^ Callosotomy is a surgical procedure that "leads to a broad breakdown of functional integration ranging from perception to attention."[147]
- ^ "Language is considered to be one of the most lateralized human brain functions. Left hemisphere dominance for language has been consistently confirmed in clinical and experimental settings and constitutes one of the main axioms of neurology and neuroscience. However, [recent] functional neuroimaging studies are finding that the right hemisphere also plays a role in diverse language functions."[15]
- ^ "Command hallucinations are widely regarded as distressing and indicative of high risk of harm to self and others [and] might be the dominant experience for individuals with a schizophrenia diagnosis[.]"[171]
- ^ "...using a variety of [neuroimaging] modalities" plus studies at the "clinical, cognitive and cellular level".[179]
General notes
[edit]- ^ All English language editions of Julian Jaynes's book retain the content, structure, and page-numbering of the original edition of 1976, which is the primary reference for the bicameral hypothesis. The third edition, published in 1990, has an extensive Afterword by the author. In this article, citations that appear only as page-numbers should be understood as referring to any English edition of Jaynes's book.
References
[edit]- ^ a b c d e f g h Jaynes, Julian (1976). The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind. Houghton Mifflin. ISBN 0-395-20729-0.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l Jaynes, Julian (1990) [1st pub. 1976; 1982]. The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind. Houghton Mifflin. ISBN 0-395-56352-6.
- ^ a b c d e Jaynes, Julian (October 1989). Verbal Hallucinations and Pre-Conscious Mentality. Presented at Harvard University Department of Psychology. First published in M. Spitzer and B.A. Maher (eds.), 1990, Philosophy and Psychopathology, New York: Springer-VerlagReprinted in Kuijsten, (2006a): Chapter 3, pages 75-94.
{{cite conference}}
: CS1 maint: location (link) CS1 maint: postscript (link) - ^ a b c d e Jaynes, Julian (April 1986). "Consciousness and the Voices of the Mind". Canadian Psychology. 27 (2).
- ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l Origin, Bk. 1, Ch. 5: The Double Brain.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i Origin, Bk. 1, Ch. 6: The Origin of Civilization.
- ^ a b c d e f g h Origin, Bk. 2, Ch. 1: Gods, Graves and Idols.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i Stove 1989.
- ^ a b c d e Kuijsten 2016.
- ^ a b c d e Limber 2006.
- ^ a b c d e f g h Origin, Bk. 3, Ch. 5: Schizophrenia.
- ^ a b c d e f g In Jaynes (1976) pp.147-313: "Book Two: The Witness of History".
- ^ a b c Kuijsten 2006a.
- ^ a b Jaynes, 1976, p. 94,168-175, 243, 300-307.
- ^ a b c d Ries, et al. 2016.
- ^ a b c d e f In Jaynes (1976) pp.315-446: "Book Three: Vestiges of the Bicameral Mind in the Modern World".
- ^ a b c d e f g h Kuijsten 2016, p. 6.
- ^ a b c d e f g h Smith 2007.
- ^ a b c Hugdahl 2009.
- ^ a b c Baumeister, et al. 2017.
- ^ a b c Waters, et al. 2018.
- ^ a b c Zeitlin 1984, p. 208-209.
- ^ a b Okuneye, et al. 2020.
- ^ McCarthy-Jones 2012.
- ^ a b c d Kuijsten 2006b.
- ^ a b c Etkin 1977.
- ^ a b c d Dennett 1986.
- ^ a b c Block 1977.
- ^ a b c d e f Jones 1979.
- ^ a b c d e f Sleutels 2006.
- ^ a b Sleutels 2006, p. 303-304.
- ^ a b c Greer 2006, p. 235.
- ^ a b c d Kuijsten 2016, p. 8.
- ^ a b c d e Woodward & Tower 2006.
- ^ a b Woodward 1979.
- ^ a b c d e f g Origin, Bk. 1, Ch. 1: The Consciousness of Consciousness.
- ^ a b c d e f Thomas 1967.
- ^ a b Landesman 1967.
- ^ a b c d Origin, "Introduction: The Problem of Consciousness".
- ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n o p q r s t u In Jaynes (1990) pp.447-469: "Afterword".
- ^ Nisbett 1977.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i Origin, Bk. 1, Ch. 2: Consciousness.
- ^ a b c d Rowe 2016c.
- ^ a b c d In Jaynes (1976) pp.19-145: "Book One: The Mind of Man".
- ^ a b c d "Summary of Evidence for Julian Jaynes's Theory". Julian Jaynes Society. Marcel Kuijsten. Retrieved 23 April 2020.
- ^ a b c d e f g h Origin, Bk. 2, Ch. 3: The Causes of Consciousness.
- ^ a b c Origin, Bk. 2, Ch. 4: A Change of Mind in Mesopotamia.
- ^ a b c d e f Origin, Bk. 2, Ch. 5: The Intellectual Consciousness of Greece.
- ^ a b Rhodes 1978.
- ^ a b c d e f Origin, Bk. 3, Ch. 1: The Quest for Authorization.
- ^ a b Origin, Bk. 3, Ch. 3: Of Poetry and Music.
- ^ a b c Origin, Bk. 3, Ch. 2: Of Prophets and Possession.
- ^ a b c Origin, Bk. 3, Ch. 4: Hypnosis.
- ^ Gibson 2016.
- ^ a b c Stove 1989, p. 271.
- ^ a b Morriss 1978.
- ^ a b c d e f g Rowe 2016a.
- ^ Stove 1989, p. 269.
- ^ Stove 1989, p. 281-286.
- ^ Rowe 2016b.
- ^ a b c Origin, Bk. 3, Ch. 6: The Auguries of Science.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Mooneyham-White 1993.
- ^ a b Rhodes 1978, p. 78.
- ^ a b c d e f Origin, Bk. 1, Ch. 3: The Mind of Iliad.
- ^ a b Marriott 1980.
- ^ Morriss 1978, p. 316.
- ^ a b Etkin 1977, p. 164.
- ^ Dennett 1986, p. 150.
- ^ Stove 1989, p. 273.
- ^ Stove 1989, p. 281.
- ^ Woodward 1979, p. 293.
- ^ Jones 1979, p. 23.
- ^ Limber 2006, p. 170.
- ^ a b Smith 2007, p. 35.
- ^ Cavanna, et al. 2007, p. 13.
- ^ Sleutels 2006, p. 330, footnote.
- ^ Dawkins 2006, p. 392-393.
- ^ a b c d e Cavanna, et al. 2007.
- ^ a b c Williams 2010.
- ^ a b Blackmore n.d.
- ^ a b c d e Luhrmann, et al. 2015.
- ^ Rowe 2016a, p. 54.
- ^ Kuijsten 2016, p. 7.
- ^ a b Rowe 2016a, p. 56.
- ^ McVeigh 2016, p. 42.
- ^ Rhodes 1978, p. 72.
- ^ Barfield 1962, p. 164-165.
- ^ Gigerenzer 2007.
- ^ a b c Kahneman 2011.
- ^ a b c d Oakley & Halligan 2017.
- ^ McVeigh 2016.
- ^ Snell 1953, p. vi.
- ^ a b c d e f g h i Origin, Bk. 2, Ch. 2: Literate Bicameral Theocracies.
- ^ a b c d e f g Origin, Bk. 2, Ch. 6: The Moral Consciousness of the Khabiru.
- ^ Snell 1953, p. 19.
- ^ a b Snell 1953.
- ^ a b c d e f g h Origin, Bk. 1, Ch. 4: The Bicameral Mind.
- ^ Snell 1953, p. 24-25.
- ^ a b Woods, et al. 2015.
- ^ a b Rowe 2016a, p. 55.
- ^ Kuijsten 2006b, p. 103.
- ^ Kuijsten 2006b, p. 116.
- ^ a b Ornstein 1973.
- ^ Carr 2006, p. 345.
- ^ Carr 2006, p. 403.
- ^ a b Carr 2006.
- ^ Gresky, et al. 2017.
- ^ Rowe 2016a, p. 65.
- ^ Emery 1961, p. 127.
- ^ Rowe 2016b, p. 80.
- ^ Rowe 2016b, p. 93-94.
- ^ Dawkins 2006, p. 393.
- ^ Sacks 2007, p. 64.
- ^ Carr 2006, p. 344.
- ^ Zeitlin 1984, p. 209-210.
- ^ The Jerusalem Bible, Reader's Edition., 1971. Doubleday & Company, Inc. New York. p. 1195
- ^ Heschel 1962, p. 192.
- ^ Heschel 1962, p. 262.
- ^ Zeitlin 1984, p. 211.
- ^ Dodds 1951.
- ^ Heschel 1962.
- ^ Heschel 1962, p. 115-130.
- ^ a b Heschel 1962, p. 119.
- ^ Woodward & Tower 2006, p. 47.
- ^ a b Limber 2006, p. 171.
- ^ a b Hacker 2012.
- ^ Smith 2007, p. 34.
- ^ a b c d Groopman 2017.
- ^ a b c "Critiques & Responses Part 1". Julian Jaynes Society. Marcel Kuijsten. Retrieved 23 April 2020.
- ^ Greer 2006, p. 239.
- ^ Sleutels 2006, p. 311.
- ^ Taube 1992.
- ^ Harris, Sam. "Making Sense #96". SamHarris.org. Sam Harris. Retrieved 27 August 2020.
- ^ a b Kuijsten 2006a, p. 3-4.
- ^ Limber 2006, p. 173.
- ^ Kuijsten 2006a, p. 4.
- ^ Buchsbaum, et al. 1982.
- ^ Asaad & Shapiro 1986.
- ^ Olin 1999.
- ^ Sher 2000.
- ^ a b Poeppel, et al. 2012.
- ^ a b c d Mitchell & Crow 2005.
- ^ a b Nathou, et al. 2019.
- ^ a b Jones 2010.
- ^ a b c Diederen, et al. 2010.
- ^ Ribolsi, et al. 2014.
- ^ de Haan, et al. 2020, p. 224.
- ^ Gazzaniga, et al. 1996.
- ^ a b de Haan, et al. 2020, p. 229.
- ^ a b de Haan, et al. 2020, p. 225.
- ^ de Haan, et al. 2020, p. 228.
- ^ a b de Haan, et al. 2020, p. 227.
- ^ Toga & Thompson 2003, p. 38.
- ^ Toga & Thompson 2003, p. 43.
- ^ Toga & Thompson 2003, p. 42.
- ^ a b Toga & Thompson 2003, p. 39.
- ^ Ribolsi, et al. 2014, p. 7.
- ^ Rentería 2012.
- ^ a b Vingerhoets 2019.
- ^ Corballis & Häberling 2017.
- ^ Xiang, et al. 2019, p. 1148.
- ^ Xiang, et al. 2019, p. 1145.
- ^ a b Xiang, et al. 2019, p. 1147.
- ^ a b Mitchell & Crow 2005, p. Abstract.
- ^ a b c d Mitchell & Crow 2005, p. 973.
- ^ Mitchell & Crow 2005, p. 974.
- ^ Sheppard & Hillis 2018, p. 3280.
- ^ Sheppard & Hillis 2018.
- ^ Waters 2014, p. p2.
- ^ Di Biase, et al. 2020.
- ^ Woods, et al. 2015, p. 329.
- ^ Beavan 2011.
- ^ Taitimu, et al. 2018.
- ^ a b McCarthy-Jones, et al. 2014.
- ^ Kuijsten 2006b, p. 120,117.
- ^ Kuijsten 2016, p. 5.
- ^ a b Ribolsi, et al. 2014, p. 6.
- ^ Steinmann, et al. 2019, p. 1.
- ^ a b Steinmann, et al. 2019, p. 88.
- ^ a b Hugdahl 2009, p. 554.
- ^ Hugdahl 2009, p. 554-555.
Bibliography
[edit]- Asaad, G.; Shapiro, B. (Sep 1986). "Hallucinations: Theoretical and Clinical Overview". American Journal of Psychiatry. 143 (9): 1088–1097. doi:10.1176/ajp.143.9.1088. PMID 2875662.
- Barfield, Owen (1962) [1926]. History in English Words (239 pgs. paper covered ed.). London: Faber and Faber Limited.
- Blackmore, Susan (n.d.). "The five best books on consciousness, recommended by Susan Blackmore" (Text interview). Interviewed by Nigel Warburton. Five Books 2021. Retrieved 4 April 2021.
- Beavan, Vanessa (2011). "Towards a definition of "hearing voices": A phenomenological approach". Psychosis. 3 (1): 63–73. doi:10.1080/17522431003615622.</ref>
- Block, Ned (March 6, 1977). "Was man really unconscious for centuries?" (PDF). The Boston Globe, (book review). p. A17.
- Block, Ned (1981). "Review of Julian Jayne's Origins [sic] of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind". Cognition and Brain Theory. 4: 81–83.
- Baumeister, D; Sedgwick, O; Howes, O; Peters, E (2017). "Auditory verbal hallucinations and continuum models of psychosis: A systematic review of the healthy voice-hearer literature". Clinical Psychology Review. 51: 125–141. doi:10.1016/j.cpr.2016.10.010.
- Buchsbaum, MS; Ingvar, DH; Kessler, R; Waters, RN; et al. (1982). "Cerebral glucography with positron tomography: Use in normal subjects and in patients with schizophrenia". Archives of General Psychiatry. 39 (3): 251–259. doi:10.1001/archpsyc.1982.04290030001001. PMID 6978119.
- Carr, Michael (2006) [1985]. "The Shi 'Corpse/Personator' Ceremony in Early China". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Reflections on the Dawn of Consciousness: Julian Jaynes's Bicameral Mind Theory Revisited. Henderson, NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 343–416. ISBN 978-0-9790744-0-0. Updated and revised from an earlier version in Computational Analyses of Asian & African Languages, 1985.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: postscript (link)
- Cavanna, AE; Trimble, M; Cinti, F; Monaco, F (2007). "The "bicameral mind" 30 years on: a critical reappraisal of Julian Jaynes' hypothesis". Functional Neurology. 22 (1): 11–15. PMID 17509238.
- Corballis, M C; Häberling, I S (2017). "The Many Sides of Hemispheric Asymmetry: A Selective Review and Outlook". Journal of the International Neuropsychological Society. 23 (9–10): 710–718. doi:10.1017/S1355617717000376.
- Dawkins, Richard (2006). The God Delusion. Houghton Mifflin. pp. 377–378. ISBN 1-4303-1230-0.
- de Haan, E H F; Corballis, P M; Hillyard, S A; Marzi, C A; Seth, A; Lamme, V A F; Volz, L; Fabri, M; Schechter, E; Bayne, T; Corballis, M; Pinto, Y (12 May 2020). "Split-Brain: What We Know Now and Why This is Important for Understanding Consciousness". Neuropsychology review. 30 (2): 224–233. doi:10.1007/s11065-020-09439-3. PMID 32399946 Revised, June 2020.
{{cite journal}}
: CS1 maint: postscript (link) - Dennett, Daniel (1986). "Julian Jaynes's Software Archeology". Canadian Psychology. 27 (2): 149–154.
- Di Biase, MA; Zhang, F; Lyall, A; et al. (Feb 2020). "Neuroimaging auditory verbal hallucinations in schizophrenia patient and healthy populations". Psychological medicine. 50 (3): 403–412. doi:10.1017/S0033291719000205. PMID 30782233.
- Diederen, KMJ; De Weijer, AD; Daalman, K; Blom, JD; Neggers, SFW; Kahn, RS; Sommer, IEC (2010). "Decreased language lateralization is characteristic of psychosis, not auditory hallucinations". Brain. 133 (12): 3734–3744. doi:10.1093/brain/awq313.
- Dodds, E.R. (1951). The Greeks and the irrational. Univ of California Press.
- Emery, Walter B. (1961). Archaic Egypt (Pelican 1972 ed.). Penguin Books.
- Etkin, William (Autumn 1977). "Review of The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind, by Julian Jaynes". Perspectives in Biology and Medicine. 21 (1): 163–165. doi:10.1353/pbm.1977.0020.
- Gazzaniga, M S; Hillyard, S A (Sep 1971). "Language and speech capacity of the right hemisphere". Neuropsychologia. 9 (3): 273–280. doi:10.1016/0028-3932(71)90022-4. PMID 5149298.
- Gazzaniga, Michael S.; Eliassen, James C.; Nisenson, Laura; Wessinger, C. Mark; Fendrich, Robert; Baynes, Kathleen (1996). "Collaboration between the hemispheres of a callosotomy patient: Emerging right hemisphere speech and the left hemisphere interpreter" (PDF). Brain. 119 (3). Center for Neuroscience, University of California Davis, Davis, California, USA: Oxford University Press: 1255–1262.
- Gibson, Todd (2016). "Listening for Ancient Voices: Julian Jaynes's Theory of the Bicameral Mind in Tibet, Part Two". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Gods, Voices, and the Bicameral Mind: The Theories of Julian Jaynes. Henderson NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 258–275. ISBN 978-0-9790744-3-1.
- Gigerenzer, Gerd (2007). Gut Feelings: The Intelligence of the Unconscious. USA: Penguin Books. ISBN 9780143113768.
- Greer, Scott (2006). "A Knowng Noos and a Slippery Psyche: Jaynes's Recipe for an Unnatural Theory of Consciousness". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Reflections on the Dawn of Consciousness: Julian Jaynes's Bicameral Mind Theory Revisited. Henderson NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 233–263. ISBN 978-0-9790744-0-0.
- Gresky, Julia; Haelm, Juliane; Clare, Lee (28 June 2017). "Modified human crania from Göbekli Tepe provide evidence for a new form of Neolithic skull cult". Science Advances. 3 (6): e1700564. doi:10.1126/sciadv.1700564. ISSN 2375-2548.
- Groopman, Jerome (January 9, 2017). "The Voices in Our Heads". New Yorker Magazine.
- Hacker, P.M.S. (2012). "The Sad and Sorry History of Consciousness: being, among other things, a challenge to the "consciousness-studies community"" (PDF). Royal Institute of Philosophy. supplementary volume 70: 1–21.
- Heschel, Abraham J. (1962). "The Theory of Ecstasy (p.115-130); Prophecy and Psychosis (p.170-189); Prophet, Priest, and King (p.254-262); Explanations of Prophetic Inspiration (p.190-205)". The Prophets (Volume II) (Harper Torchbooks Paperback, 1975 ed.). Harper & Row. ISBN 0-06-131557-5.
- Holderness, Mike (July 17, 1993). "Review: In two minds about consciousness". New Scientist (1882): 139.
- Hugdahl, Kenneth (2009). "Hearing voices: Auditory hallucinations as failure of top-down control of bottom-up perceptual processes". Scandinavian Journal of Psychology. 50: 553–560. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9450.2009.00775.x.
- Jaynes, Julian (1976). The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind. Houghton Mifflin. ISBN 0-395-20729-0.
- Jaynes, Julian (April 1986). "Consciousness and the Voices of the Mind". Canadian Psychology. 27 (2).
- Jaynes, Julian (October 1989). "Verbal Hallucinations and Preconscious Mentality". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Reflections on the Dawn of Consciousness: Julian Jaynes's Bicameral Mind Theory Revisited. Henderson NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 75–94. ISBN 978-0-9790744-0-0. Presented at Harvard University Department of Psychology. First published in M. Spitzer and B.A. Maher (eds.), 1990, Philosophy and Psychopathology, New York: Springer-Verlag.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: postscript (link)
- Jaynes, Julian (1990) [1976]. The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind. Houghton Mifflin. ISBN 0-395-56352-6.
- Jaynes, Julian (2000) [1976; 1990]. The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind (PDF). Houghton Mifflin, Mariner Books edition. ISBN 0-618-05707-2.
- Jones, Simon R. (May 2010). "Do We Need Multiple Models of Auditory Verbal Hallucinations? Examining the Phenomenological Fit of Cognitive and Neurological Models". Schizophrenia Bulletin. 36 (3): 566–575. doi:10.1093/schbul/sbn129.
- Jones, William Thomas (1979), "Mr. Jaynes and the bicameral mind: a case study in the sociology of belief", Humanities Working Paper, 23, California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, CA.
- Kahneman, Daniel (2011). Thinking, Fast and Slow. UK: Penguin Random House. ISBN 9780141033570.
- Koch, Sigmund (1967). "Behaviourism". Encyclopaedia Britannica. Vol. 3. pp. 398–403.
- Kuijsten, Marcel (2006a). "Introduction". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Reflections on the Dawn of Consciousness: Julian Jaynes's Bicameral Mind Theory Revisited. Henderson NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 1–10. ISBN 978-0-9790744-0-0.
- Kuijsten, Marcel (2006b). "Consciousness, Hallucinations, and the Bicameral Mind: Three Decades of New Research". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Reflections on the Dawn of Consciousness: Julian Jaynes's Bicameral Mind Theory Revisited. Henderson NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 95–140. ISBN 978-0-9790744-0-0.
- Kuijsten, Marcel (2016). "Introduction". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Gods, Voices, and the Bicameral Mind: The Theories of Julian Jaynes. Henderson NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 1–15. ISBN 978-0-9790744-3-1.
- Landesman, Charles, Jr. (1967). "Consciousness". In Edwards, Paul (ed.). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 2 (Reprint 1972 ed.). Macmillan, Inc. pp. 191–195.
{{cite encyclopedia}}
: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
- Limber, John E. (2006). "Language and consciousness: Jaynes's "preposterous idea" reconsidered". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Reflections on the Dawn of Consciousness: Julian Jaynes's Bicameral Mind Theory Revisited. Henderson, NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 169–202.
- Luhrmann, Tanya M.; Padmavati, R.; Tharoor, Hema; Osei, Akwasi (September 8, 2015). "Hearing Voices in Different Cultures: A Social Kindling Hypothesis". Topics in Cognitive Science. doi:10.1111/tops.12158.
- Marriott, F.H.C. (Spring 1980). "The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind by Julian Jaynes (review)". Leonardo. 13 (2). The MIT Press: 157–158.
- McCarthy-Jones, Simon (2012). Hearing voices: the histories, causes, and meanings of auditory verbal hallucinations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9781139017534.
- McCarthy-Jones, Simon (2014). "Better than mermaids and stray dogs? Subtyping auditory verbal hallucinations and its implications for research and practice". Schizophrenia bulletin. 40 (Suppl 4, (Suppl 4)): S275-284. doi:10.1093/schbul/sbu018. PMID 31413576.
- McVeigh, Brian J. (2016). "Elephants in the Psychology Department:Overcoming Intellectual Barriers to Understanding Julian Jaynes's Theory". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Gods, Voices, and the Bicameral Mind: The Theories of Julian Jaynes. Henderson NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 38–53. ISBN 978-0-9790744-3-1.
- Mitchell, Rachel L. C.; Crow, Tim J. (2005). "Right hemisphere language functions and schizophrenia: the forgotten hemisphere?". Brain. 28 (5): 963–978. doi:10.1093/brain/awh466.
- Mooneyham-White, Laura (July 1993). "The origin of consciousness, gains and losses: Walker Percy vs Julian Jaynes". Language and Communication. 13 (3): 169–182. doi:10.1016/0271-5309(93)90024-H. ISSN 0271-5309. (Reprinted in Kuijsten, M. (ed.), Gods, Voices and the Bicameral Mind, 2016, pp. 175-197.)
{{cite journal}}
: CS1 maint: postscript (link) - Morriss, James E. (1978). "Reflections on Julian Jaynes's THE ORIGIN OF CONSCIOUSNESS IN THE BREAKDOWN OF THE BICAMERAL MIND: An Essay Review" (PDF). ETC: A Review of General Semantics. 35 (3): 314–327.
- Nathou, C; Etard, O; Dollfus, S (July 24, 2019). "Auditory verbal hallucinations in schizophrenia: current perspectives in brain stimulation treatments". Neuropsychiatric disease and treatment. 15: 2105–2117. doi:10.2147/NDT.S168801. PMID 31413576.
{{cite journal}}
: CS1 maint: unflagged free DOI (link) - Nisbett, Richard E.; Wilson, Timothy D. (1977). "Telling more than we can know: Verbal reports on mental processes". Psychological Review. 84 (3): 231–259. doi:10.1037/0033-295x.84.3.231. hdl:2027.42/92167. reprinted in David Lewis Hamilton, ed. (2005). Social cognition: key readings. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-86377-591-8.
- Oakley, David A; Halligan, Peter W (2017). "Chasing the Rainbow: The Non-conscious Nature of Being". Frontiers in Psychology. 8: 19–24. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01924. ISSN 1664-1078.
{{cite journal}}
: CS1 maint: unflagged free DOI (link) - Okuneye, VT; Meda, S; Pearlson, GD; Clementz, BA; Keshavan, MS; Tamminga, CA; Ivleva, E; Sweeney, JA; Gershon, ES; Keedy, SK (July 22, 2020). "Resting state auditory-language cortex connectivity is associated with hallucinations in clinical and biological subtypes of psychotic disorders". Neuroimage: Clinical,. 2020, 27:102358. doi:10.1016/j.nicl.2020.102358. PMID 32745995.
{{cite journal}}
: CS1 maint: extra punctuation (link)
- Olin, Robert (1999). "Auditory hallucinations and the bicameral mind". Lancet. 354 (9173): 166. doi:10.1016/S0140-6736(05)75304-6. PMID 10408523.
- Ornstein, Robert E., ed. (1973). The Nature of Human Consciousness (A Book of Readings). New York, USA: Viking Adult. ISBN 0-670-50480-7.
- Poeppel, David; Emmorey, Karen; Hickok, Gregory; Pylkkänen, Liina (10 October 2012). "Towards a New Neurobiology of Language". The Journal of neuroscience : the official journal of the Society for Neuroscience. 32 (41): 14125–14131. doi:10.1523/JNEUROSCI.3244-12.2012.
- Rentería, Miguel E (2012). "Cerebral Asymmetry: A Quantitative, Multifactorial, and Plastic Brain Phenotype". Twin Research and Human Genetics. 15 (3): 401–413. doi:10.1017/thg.2012.13.
- Rhodes, Richard (January–February 1978). "Alone in the country of the mind: the origin of Julian Jaynes (Interview)". Quest/78. 2 (1). Pasadena: Ambassador International Cultural Foundation: 71–78.
{{cite journal}}
: CS1 maint: date format (link)
- Ribolsi, M; Daskalakis, ZJ; Siracusano, A; Koch, G (22 December 2014). "Abnormal asymmetry of brain connectivity in schizophrenia". Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 8 (Article 1010). doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.01010. PMC 4273663.
{{cite journal}}
: CS1 maint: PMC format (link) CS1 maint: unflagged free DOI (link) - Riès, Stéphanie K.; Dronkers, Nina F.; Knight, Robert T. (April 2016) [14 January 2016]. "Choosing words: left hemisphere, right hemisphere, or both? Perspective on the lateralization of word retrieval". Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences. 1369 (1): 111–131. doi:10.1111/nyas.12993.
- Rowe, Bill (2016a). "Voices Become Gods". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Gods, Voices, and the Bicameral Mind: The Theories of Julian Jaynes. Henderson NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 54–77. ISBN 978-0-9790744-3-1.
- Rowe, Bill (2016b). "The Ancient Dark Age". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Gods, Voices, and the Bicameral Mind: The Theories of Julian Jaynes. Henderson NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 78–94. ISBN 978-0-9790744-3-1 (Portions first appeared in American Journal of Psychology, 2012, Vol.125, 1-4.)
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: postscript (link) - Rowe, Bill (2016c). "Two Origins of Consciousness". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Gods, Voices, and the Bicameral Mind: The Theories of Julian Jaynes. Henderson NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 155–174. ISBN 978-0-9790744-3-1.
- Sacks, Oliver (2007). Musicophilia: Tales of Music and the Brain.
- Sheppard, Shannon M.; Hillis, Argye E. (December 2018). "That's right! Language comprehension beyond the left hemisphere". Brain. 141 (12): 3280–3282. doi:10.1093/brain/awy291.
- Sher, Leo (May 2000). "Neuroimaging, auditory hallucinations, and the bicameral mind". Journal of Psychiatry and Neuroscience. 25 (3): 239–240. PMC 1407719. PMID 10863883.
- Sleutels, J.J.M. (2006). "Greek Zombies: On the alleged absurdity of substantially unconscious Greek minds". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Reflections on the Dawn of Consciousness: Julian Jaynes's Bicameral Mind Theory Revisited. Henderson, NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 303–335. S2CID 220329899. First published in Philosophical Psychology, 2006, 19,2. (pp. 177-197)
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: postscript (link)
- Smith, Daniel B. (2007). Muses, Madmen, and Prophets: Rethinking the history, science, and meaning of auditory hallucination. Penguin Books. ISBN 1-59420-110-2.
- Snell, Bruno (1953). The Discovery of the Mind: the Greek Origins of European Thought (English transl. by T.G. Rosenmeyer, from the German Die Entdeckung des Geistes [1948] ed.). Oxford, Basil Blackwell.
- Sommer, Iris E.C. (2008). "Auditory verbal hallucinations predominantly activate the right inferior frontal area" (PDF). Brain: a journal of neurology. 131 (Pt. 12): 3169–3177. doi:10.1093/brain/awn251.
- Sommer, Iris E.; Diederen, Kelly M. (October 2009). "Language production in the non-dominant hemisphere as a potential source of auditory verbal hallucinations". Brain. 132 (10): e124. doi:10.1093/brain/awp040.
- Steinmann, Saskia; Leicht, Gregor; Mulert, Christoph (February 2019). "The interhemispheric miscommunication theory of auditory verbal hallucinations in schizophrenia". International Journal of Psychophysiology. 145: 83–90. doi:10.1016/j.ijpsycho.2019.02.002.
- Stove, David C. (1989) [First published in Encounter, April 1989, Vol. 72]. "The Oracles and Their Cessation: A Tribute to Julian Jaynes". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Reflections on the Dawn of Consciousness: Julian Jaynes's Bicameral Mind Theory Revisited. Henderson NV: Julian Jaynes Society (published 2006). pp. 267–294. ISBN 978-0-9790744-0-0.
- Taitimu, Melissa; Read, John; McIntosh, Tracey (2018-02-19). "Ngā Whakāwhitinga (standing at the crossroads): How Māori understand what Western psychiatry calls "schizophrenia"". Transcultural Psychiatry. 55 (2): 153–177. doi:10.1177/1363461518757800. ISSN 1363-4615.
- Taube, Karl A. (1992). "The Iconography of Mirrors at Teotihuacan". In Janet Catherine Berlo (ed.). Art, Ideology, and the City of Teotihuacan: A Symposium at Dumbarton Oaks, 8th and 9th October 1988. Washington, D.C.: Dumbarton Oaks Research Library and Collections and Trustees of Harvard University. pp. 169–204. ISBN 978-0-88402-205-3. OCLC 25547129.
- Thomas, Garth J. (1967). "Consciousness". Encyclopaedia Britannica. Vol. 6. pp. 364–366.
- Toga, Arthur W.; Thompson, Paul M. (January 2003). "Mapping Brain Asymmetry". Nature Reviews Neuroscience. 4: 37–48. doi:10.1038/nrn1009.
- Vingerhoets, Guy (2019). "Phenotypes in hemispheric functional segregation? Perspectives and challenges". Physics of life reviews. 30: 1–18. doi:10.1016/j.plrev.2019.06.002.
- Waters, Flavie (December 30, 2014). "Auditory Hallucinations in Adult Populations". Psychiatric Times. 31 (12).
- Waters, F.; Blom, J.; Jardri, R.; Hugdahl, K.; Sommer, I. (2018). "Auditory hallucinations, not necessarily a hallmark of psychotic disorder". Psychological Medicine. 48 (4): 529–536. doi:10.1017/S0033291717002203.
- Williams, Gary (2010). "What is it like to be nonconscious? A defense of Julian Jaynes". Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. 10 (2): 217–239. doi:10.1007/s11097-010-9181-z.
- Woods, A; Jones, N; Alderson-Day, B; Callard, F; Fernyhough, C (April 2015). "Experiences of hearing voices: analysis of a novel phenomenological survey [published correction appears in Lancet Psychiatry. 2015 May;2(5):378]". Lancet Psychiatry. 2: 323–331. doi:10.1016/S2215-0366(15)00006-1.
- Woodward, William R. (June 1979). "Book Review: The Origin of Consciousness in the Breakdown of the Bicameral Mind. Julian Jaynes". ISIS. 70 (2). The University of Chicago Press: 292–293. doi:10.1086/352224.
- Woodward, William R.; Tower, June F. (2006). "Julian Jaynes: Introducing His Life and Thought". In Kuijsten, Marcel (ed.). Reflections on the Dawn of Consciousness: Julian Jaynes's Bicameral Mind Theory Revisited. Henderson, NV: Julian Jaynes Society. pp. 13–68. ISBN 978-0-9790744-0-0.
- Xiang, L; Crow, T; Roberts, N (2019). "Cerebral torque is human specific and unrelated to brain size". Brain structure & function. 224 (3): 1141–1150. doi:10.1007/s00429-018-01818-0. PMC 6499874.
{{cite journal}}
: CS1 maint: PMC format (link) - Zeitlin, Irving M. (1984). Ancient Judaism: Biblical Criticism from Max Weber to the present (1991 Reprint ed.). Cambridge, UK: Polity Press. ISBN 0-7456-0297-5.
See also
[edit]Mirrors in Mesoamerican culture
External links
[edit]- William Woodward, historian of psychology, and biographer.
- Marcel Kuijsten, a student of Jaynes’s and founder of the Julian Jaynes Society.
- Jan Sleutels, philosopher.
- John E. Limber, psycholinguist.
- Laura Mooneyham White, English professor and literary theorist.
- Consciousness Studies, a non-Jaynesian approach to consciousness.