Jump to content

Relationship between mathematics and physics

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

A cycloidal pendulum is isochronous, a fact discovered and proved by Christiaan Huygens under certain mathematical assumptions.[1]
Mathematics was developed by the Ancient Civilizations for intellectual challenge and pleasure. Surprisingly, many of their discoveries later played prominent roles in physical theories, as in the case of the conic sections in celestial mechanics.

The relationship between mathematics and physics has been a subject of study of philosophers, mathematicians and physicists since antiquity, and more recently also by historians and educators.[2] Generally considered a relationship of great intimacy,[3] mathematics has been described as "an essential tool for physics"[4] and physics has been described as "a rich source of inspiration and insight in mathematics".[5] Some of the oldest and most discussed themes are about the main differences between the two subjects, their mutual influence, the role of mathematical rigor in physics, and the problem of explaining the effectiveness of mathematics in physics.

In his work Physics, one of the topics treated by Aristotle is about how the study carried out by mathematicians differs from that carried out by physicists.[6] Considerations about mathematics being the language of nature can be found in the ideas of the Pythagoreans: the convictions that "Numbers rule the world" and "All is number",[7][8] and two millennia later were also expressed by Galileo Galilei: "The book of nature is written in the language of mathematics".[9][10]

Historical interplay

[edit]

Before giving a mathematical proof for the formula for the volume of a sphere, Archimedes used physical reasoning to discover the solution (imagining the balancing of bodies on a scale).[11] Aristotle classified physics and mathematics as theoretical sciences, in contrast to practical sciences (like ethics or politics) and to productive sciences (like medicine or botany).[12]

From the seventeenth century, many of the most important advances in mathematics appeared motivated by the study of physics, and this continued in the following centuries (although in the nineteenth century mathematics started to become increasingly independent from physics).[13][14] The creation and development of calculus were strongly linked to the needs of physics:[15] There was a need for a new mathematical language to deal with the new dynamics that had arisen from the work of scholars such as Galileo Galilei and Isaac Newton.[16] The concept of derivative was needed, Newton did not have the modern concept of limits, and instead employed infinitesimals, which lacked a rigorous foundation at that time.[17] During this period there was little distinction between physics and mathematics;[18] as an example, Newton regarded geometry as a branch of mechanics.[19]

In the 19th century Auguste Comte in his hierarchy of the sciences, placed physics and astronomy as less general and more complex than mathematics, as both depend on it.[20] In 1900, David Hilbert in his 23 problems for the advancement of mathematical science, considered the axiomatization of physics as his sixth problem. The problem remains open.[21]

The mathematical rigor of Dirac's delta function was in doubt until the works of Laurent Schwartz on the theory of distributions.[22]

As time progressed, the mathematics used in physics has become increasingly sophisticated, as in the case of superstring theory.[23] Unconventional connections between the two fields are found all the time as in 1975 Wu–Yang dictionary, that related concepts of gauge theory with differential geometry.[24]

Physics is not mathematics

[edit]

Despite the close relationship between math and physics, they are not synonyms. In mathematics objects can be defined exactly and logically related, but the object need have no relationship to experimental measurements. In physics, definitions are abstractions or idealizations, approximations adequate when compared to the natural world. For example, Newton built a physical model around definitions like his second law of motion based on observations, leading to the development of calculus and highly accurate planetary mechanics, but later this definition was superseded by improved models of mechanics.[25] Mathematics deals with entities whose properties can be known with certainty.[26] According to David Hume, only in logic and mathematics statements can be proved (being known with total certainty). While in the physical world one can never know the properties of its beings in an absolute or complete way, leading to a situation that was put by Albert Einstein as "No number of experiments can prove me right; a single experiment can prove me wrong."[27] The ultimate goal in research in pure mathematics are rigorous proofs, while in physics heuristic arguments may sometimes suffice in leading-edge research.[28] In short, the methods and goals of physicists and mathematicians are different.[29] Nonetheless, according to Roland Omnès, the axioms of mathematics are not mere conventions, but have physical origins.[30]

Role of rigor in physics

[edit]

Rigor is indispensable in pure mathematics.[31] But many definitions and arguments found in the physics literature involve concepts and ideas that are not up to the standards of rigor in mathematics.[28][32][33][34]

Philosophical problems

[edit]

Some of the problems considered in the philosophy of mathematics are the following:

  • Explain the effectiveness of mathematics in the study of the physical world: "At this point an enigma presents itself which in all ages has agitated inquiring minds. How can it be that mathematics, being after all a product of human thought which is independent of experience, is so admirably appropriate to the objects of reality?" —Albert Einstein, in Geometry and Experience (1921).[35]
  • Clearly delineate mathematics and physics: For some results or discoveries, it is difficult to say to which area they belong: to the mathematics or to physics.[36]
  • What is the geometry of physical space?[37]
  • What is the origin of the axioms of mathematics?[38]
  • How does the already existing mathematics influence in the creation and development of physical theories?[39]
  • Is arithmetic analytic or synthetic? (from Kant, see Analytic–synthetic distinction)[40]
  • What is essentially different between doing a physical experiment to see the result and making a mathematical calculation to see the result? (from the TuringWittgenstein debate)[41]
  • Do Gödel's incompleteness theorems imply that physical theories will always be incomplete? (from Stephen Hawking)[42][43]
  • Is mathematics invented or discovered? (millennia-old question, raised among others by Mario Livio)[44]

Education

[edit]

In recent times the two disciplines have most often been taught separately, despite all the interrelations between physics and mathematics.[45] This led some professional mathematicians who were also interested in mathematics education, such as Felix Klein, Richard Courant, Vladimir Arnold and Morris Kline, to strongly advocate teaching mathematics in a way more closely related to the physical sciences.[46][47] The initial courses of mathematics for college students of physics are often taught by mathematicians, despite the differences in "ways of thinking" of physicists and mathematicians about those traditional courses and how they are used in the physics courses classes thereafter.[48]

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Jed Z. Buchwald; Robert Fox (10 October 2013). The Oxford Handbook of the History of Physics. OUP Oxford. p. 128. ISBN 978-0-19-151019-9.
  2. ^ Uhden, Olaf; Karam, Ricardo; Pietrocola, Maurício; Pospiech, Gesche (20 October 2011). "Modelling Mathematical Reasoning in Physics Education". Science & Education. 21 (4): 485–506. Bibcode:2012Sc&Ed..21..485U. doi:10.1007/s11191-011-9396-6. S2CID 122869677.
  3. ^ Francis Bailly; Giuseppe Longo (2011). Mathematics and the Natural Sciences: The Physical Singularity of Life. World Scientific. p. 149. ISBN 978-1-84816-693-6.
  4. ^ Sanjay Moreshwar Wagh; Dilip Abasaheb Deshpande (27 September 2012). Essentials of Physics. PHI Learning Pvt. Ltd. p. 3. ISBN 978-81-203-4642-0.
  5. ^ Atiyah, Michael (1990). On the Work of Edward Witten (PDF). International Congress of Mathematicians. Japan. pp. 31–35. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2017-03-01.
  6. ^ Lear, Jonathan (1990). Aristotle: the desire to understand (Repr. ed.). Cambridge [u.a.]: Cambridge Univ. Press. p. 232. ISBN 9780521347624.
  7. ^ Gerard Assayag; Hans G. Feichtinger; José-Francisco Rodrigues (10 July 2002). Mathematics and Music: A Diderot Mathematical Forum. Springer. p. 216. ISBN 978-3-540-43727-7.
  8. ^ Al-Rasasi, Ibrahim (21 June 2004). "All is number" (PDF). King Fahd University of Petroleum and Minerals. Archived from the original (PDF) on 28 December 2014. Retrieved 13 June 2015.
  9. ^ Aharon Kantorovich (1 July 1993). Scientific Discovery: Logic and Tinkering. SUNY Press. p. 59. ISBN 978-0-7914-1478-1.
  10. ^ Kyle Forinash, William Rumsey, Chris Lang, Galileo's Mathematical Language of Nature Archived 2013-09-27 at the Wayback Machine.
  11. ^ Arthur Mazer (26 September 2011). The Ellipse: A Historical and Mathematical Journey. John Wiley & Sons. p. 5. Bibcode:2010ehmj.book.....M. ISBN 978-1-118-21143-4.
  12. ^ Shields, Christopher (2023), "Aristotle", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2023 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2024-11-11
  13. ^ E. J. Post, A History of Physics as an Exercise in Philosophy, p. 76.
  14. ^ Arkady Plotnitsky, Niels Bohr and Complementarity: An Introduction, p. 177.
  15. ^ Roger G. Newton (1997). The Truth of Science: Physical Theories and Reality. Harvard University Press. pp. 125–126. ISBN 978-0-674-91092-8.
  16. ^ Eoin P. O'Neill (editor), What Did You Do Today, Professor?: Fifteen Illuminating Responses from Trinity College Dublin, p. 62.
  17. ^ Rédei, M. "On the Tension Between Physics and Mathematics". J Gen Philos Sci 51, pp. 411–425 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-019-09496-0
  18. ^ Timothy Gowers; June Barrow-Green; Imre Leader (18 July 2010). The Princeton Companion to Mathematics. Princeton University Press. p. 7. ISBN 978-1-4008-3039-8.
  19. ^ David E. Rowe (2008). "Euclidean Geometry and Physical Space". The Mathematical Intelligencer. 28 (2): 51–59. doi:10.1007/BF02987157. S2CID 56161170.
  20. ^ Bourdeau, Michel (2023), "Auguste Comte", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2023 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2024-11-08
  21. ^ Gorban, A. N. (2018-04-28). "Hilbert's sixth problem: the endless road to rigour". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences. 376 (2118): 20170238. doi:10.1098/rsta.2017.0238. ISSN 1364-503X. PMC 5869544. PMID 29555808.
  22. ^ "The coevolution of physics and math", Symmetry Magazine, April 24, 2018
  23. ^ "String theories". Particle Central. Four Peaks Technologies. Retrieved 13 June 2015.
  24. ^ Zeidler, Eberhard (2008-09-03). Quantum Field Theory II: Quantum Electrodynamics: A Bridge between Mathematicians and Physicists. Springer Science & Business Media. ISBN 978-3-540-85377-0.
  25. ^ Feynman, Richard P. (2011). "Characteristics of Force". The Feynman lectures on physics. Volume 1: Mainly mechanics, radiation, and heat (The new millennium edition, paperback first published ed.). New York: Basic Books. ISBN 978-0-465-02493-3.
  26. ^ Ernest, Paul (2003). The philosophy of mathematics education. Studies in mathematics education (Transferred to digital printing 2005; [Reprint of the ed. 1991] ed.). New York, NY: Routledge. ISBN 978-1-85000-667-1.
  27. ^ Fundamentals of Physics - Volume 2 - Page 627, by David Halliday, Robert Resnick, Jearl Walker (1993)
  28. ^ a b MICHAEL ATIYAH ET AL. "RESPONSES TO THEORETICAL MATHEMATICS: TOWARD A CULTURAL SYNTHESIS OF MATHEMATICS AND THEORETICAL PHYSICS, BY A. JAFFE AND F. QUINN. https://www.ams.org/journals/bull/1994-30-02/S0273-0979-1994-00503-8/S0273-0979-1994-00503-8.pdf"
  29. ^ Redish, Edward F.; Kuo, Eric (2015-07-01). "Language of Physics, Language of Math: Disciplinary Culture and Dynamic Epistemology". Science & Education. 24 (5): 561–590. doi:10.1007/s11191-015-9749-7. ISSN 1573-1901.
  30. ^ Roland Omnès (2005) Converging Realities: Toward a Common Philosophy of Physics and Mathematics p. 38 and p. 215
  31. ^ Steven Weinberg, To Explain the World: The Discovery of Modern Science, pp. 9–10.
  32. ^ Kevin Davey. "Is Mathematical Rigor Necessary in Physics?", The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 54, No. 3 (Sep., 2003), pp. 439–463 https://www.jstor.org/stable/3541794
  33. ^ Mark Steiner (1992), "Mathematical Rigor in Physics". https://www.taylorfrancis.com/chapters/edit/10.4324/9780203979105-13/mathematical-rigor-physics-mark-steiner
  34. ^ P.W. Bridgman (1959), "How Much Rigor is Possible in Physics?" https://doi.org/10.1016/S0049-237X(09)70030-8
  35. ^ Albert Einstein, Geometry and Experience.
  36. ^ Pierre Bergé, Des rythmes au chaos.
  37. ^ Gary Carl Hatfield (1990). The Natural and the Normative: Theories of Spatial Perception from Kant to Helmholtz. MIT Press. p. 223. ISBN 978-0-262-08086-6.
  38. ^ Gila Hanna; Hans Niels Jahnke; Helmut Pulte (4 December 2009). Explanation and Proof in Mathematics: Philosophical and Educational Perspectives. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 29–30. ISBN 978-1-4419-0576-5.
  39. ^ "FQXi Community Trick or Truth: the Mysterious Connection Between Physics and Mathematics". Archived from the original on 14 December 2021. Retrieved 16 April 2015.
  40. ^ James Van Cleve Professor of Philosophy Brown University (16 July 1999). Problems from Kant. Oxford University Press, USA. p. 22. ISBN 978-0-19-534701-2.
  41. ^ Ludwig Wittgenstein; R. G. Bosanquet; Cora Diamond (15 October 1989). Wittgenstein's Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics, Cambridge, 1939. University of Chicago Press. p. 96. ISBN 978-0-226-90426-9.
  42. ^ Pudlák, Pavel (2013). Logical Foundations of Mathematics and Computational Complexity: A Gentle Introduction. Springer Science & Business Media. p. 659. ISBN 978-3-319-00119-7.
  43. ^ "Stephen Hawking. "Godel and the End of the Universe"". Archived from the original on 2020-05-29. Retrieved 2015-06-12.
  44. ^ Mario Livio (August 2011). "Why math works?". Scientific American: 80–83.
  45. ^ Karam; Pospiech; & Pietrocola (2010). "Mathematics in physics lessons: developing structural skills"
  46. ^ Stakhov "Dirac’s Principle of Mathematical Beauty, Mathematics of Harmony"
  47. ^ Richard Lesh; Peter L. Galbraith; Christopher R. Haines; Andrew Hurford (2009). Modeling Students' Mathematical Modeling Competencies: ICTMA 13. Springer. p. 14. ISBN 978-1-4419-0561-1.
  48. ^ https://bridge.math.oregonstate.edu/papers/ampere.pdf

Further reading

[edit]
[edit]