Metalogic: Difference between revisions
Appearance
Content deleted Content added
Laurahappy85 (talk | contribs) ←Replaced content with 'not reliable sources. page must be deleted, end of story' |
|||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
not reliable sources. |
|||
'''Metalogic''' is the study of the [[metatheory]] of [[logic]]. While ''logic'' is the study of the manner in which [[logical system]]s can be used to decide the correctness of arguments, metalogic studies the properties of the logical systems themselves.<ref>[[Harry J. Gensler]], Introduction to Logic, Routledge, 2001, p. 253.</ref> According to [[Geoffrey Hunter (logician)|Geoffrey Hunter]], while logic concerns itself with the "truths of logic," metalogic concerns itself with the theory of "sentences used to express truths of logic."<ref name="metalogic">[[Geoffrey Hunter (logician)|Hunter, Geoffrey]], ''Metalogic: An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First-Order Logic'', University of California Press, 1971</ref> |
|||
page must be deleted, end of story |
|||
The basic objects of study in metalogic are [[formal language]]s, [[formal system]]s, and their [[Interpretation (logic)|interpretations]]. The study of interpretation of formal systems is the branch of [[mathematical logic]] known as [[model theory]], while the study of [[deductive apparatus]] is the branch known as [[proof theory]]. |
|||
== History == |
|||
Metalogical questions have been asked since the time of [[Aristotle]]. However, it was only with the rise of formal languages in the late 19th and early 20th century that investigations into the foundations of logic began to flourish. In 1904, [[David Hilbert]] observed that in investigating the [[foundations of mathematics]] that logical notions are presupposed, and therefore a simultaneous account of metalogical and [[metamathematics|metamathematical]] principles was required. Today, metalogic and metamathematics are largely synonymous with each other, and both have been substantially subsumed by [[mathematical logic]] in academia. |
|||
== Important distinctions in metalogic == |
|||
=== Metalanguage–Object language === |
|||
{{Main|Metalanguage|Object language}} |
|||
In metalogic, formal languages are sometimes called ''object languages''. The language used to make statements about an object language is called a ''metalanguage''. This distinction is a key difference between logic and metalogic. While logic deals with ''proofs in a formal system'', expressed in some formal language, metalogic deals with ''proofs about a formal system'' which are expressed in a metalanguage about some object language. |
|||
=== Syntax–semantics === |
|||
{{Main|Syntax (logic)|Formal semantics (logic)}} |
|||
In metalogic, 'syntax' has to do with formal languages or formal systems without regard to any interpretation of them, whereas, 'semantics' has to do with interpretations of formal languages. The term 'syntactic' has a slightly wider scope than 'proof-theoretic', since it may be applied to properties of formal languages without any deductive systems, as well as to formal systems. 'Semantic' is synonymous with 'model-theoretic'. |
|||
=== Use–mention === |
|||
{{Main|Use–mention distinction}} |
|||
In metalogic, the words 'use' and 'mention', in both their noun and verb forms, take on a technical sense in order to identify an important distinction.<ref name="metalogic"/> The ''use–mention distinction'' (sometimes referred to as the ''words-as-words distinction'') is the distinction between ''using'' a word (or phrase) and ''mentioning'' it. Usually it is indicated that an expression is being mentioned rather than used by enclosing it in quotation marks, printing it in italics, or setting the expression by itself on a line. The enclosing in quotes of an expression gives us the [[name]] of an expression, for example: |
|||
:'Metalogic' is the name of this article. |
|||
:This article is about metalogic. |
|||
=== Type–token === |
|||
{{Main|Type-token distinction}} |
|||
The ''type-token distinction'' is a distinction in metalogic, that separates an abstract concept from the objects which are particular instances of the concept. For example, the particular bicycle in your garage is a token of the [[type (metaphysics)|type]] of thing known as "The bicycle." Whereas, the bicycle in your garage is in a particular place at a particular time, that is not true of "the bicycle" as used in the sentence: "''The bicycle'' has become more popular recently." This distinction is used to clarify the meaning of [[symbol (formal)|symbols]] of [[formal language]]s. |
|||
== Overview == |
|||
=== Formal language === |
|||
{{Main|Formal language}} |
|||
A ''formal language'' is an organized set of [[symbol (formal)|symbols]] the essential feature of which is that it can |
|||
be precisely defined in terms of just the shapes and locations of those symbols. Such a language can be defined, then, without any [[reference]] to any [[meaning (linguistics)|meanings]] of any of its expressions; it can exist before any [[Interpretation (logic)|interpretation]] is assigned to it—that is, before it has any meaning. First order logic is expressed in some formal language. A formal grammar determines which symbols and sets of symbols are [[Formula (mathematical logic)|formulas]] in a formal language. |
|||
A formal language can be defined formally as a set ''A'' of strings (finite sequences) on a fixed alphabet α. Some authors, including Carnap, define the language as the ordered pair <α, ''A''>.<ref name="itslaia">[[Rudolf Carnap]] (1958) ''Introduction to Symbolic Logic and its Applications'', p. 102.</ref> Carnap also requires that each element of α must occur in at least one string in ''A''. |
|||
=== Formation rules === |
|||
{{Main|Formation rules}} |
|||
''Formation rules'' (also called ''formal grammar'') are a precise description of the [[well-formed formula]]s of a formal language. It is synonymous with the [[set (mathematics)|set]] of [[String (computer science)|strings]] over the [[alphabet]] of the formal language which constitute well formed formulas. However, it does not describe their [[semantics]] (i.e. what they mean). |
|||
=== Formal systems === |
|||
{{Main|Formal system}} |
|||
A ''formal system'' (also called a ''logical calculus'', or a ''logical system'') consists of a formal language together with a [[deductive apparatus]] (also called a ''deductive system''). The deductive apparatus may consist of a set of [[transformation rule]]s (also called ''inference rules'') or a set of [[axiom]]s, or have both. A formal system is used to [[Proof theory|derive]] one expression from one or more other expressions. |
|||
A ''formal system'' can be formally defined as an ordered triple <α,<math>\mathcal{I}</math>,<math>\mathcal{D}</math>d>, where <math>\mathcal{D}</math>d is the relation of direct derivability. This relation is understood in a comprehensive [[Sense and reference|sense]] such that the primitive sentences of the formal system are taken as directly [[formal proof|derivable]] from the [[empty set]] of sentences. Direct derivability is a relation between a sentence and a finite, possibly empty set of sentences. Axioms are laid down in such a way that every first place member of <math>\mathcal{D}</math>d is a member of <math>\mathcal{I}</math> and every second place member is a finite subset of <math>\mathcal{I}</math>. |
|||
It is also possible to define a ''formal system'' using only the relation <math>\mathcal{D}</math>d. In this way we can omit <math>\mathcal{I}</math>, and α in the definitions of ''interpreted formal language'', and ''interpreted formal system''. However, this method can be more difficult to understand and work with.<ref name = "itslaia"/> |
|||
=== Formal proofs === |
|||
{{Main|Formal proof}} |
|||
A ''formal proof'' is a sequence of well-formed formulas of a formal language, the last one of which is a [[theorem]] of a formal system. The theorem is a [[syntactic consequence]] of all the well formed formulae preceding it in the proof. For a well formed formula to qualify as part of a proof, it must be the result of applying a rule of the deductive apparatus of some formal system to the previous well formed formulae in the proof sequence. |
|||
=== Interpretations === |
|||
{{Main|Interpretation (logic)|Formal semantics (logic)}} |
|||
An ''interpretation'' of a formal system is the assignment of meanings, to the symbols, and [[truth-value]]s to the sentences of the formal system. The study of interpretations is called [[Formal semantics (logic)|Formal semantics]]. ''Giving an interpretation'' is synonymous with ''constructing a [[Structure (mathematical logic)|model]]. |
|||
== Results in metalogic == |
|||
Results in metalogic consist of such things as [[formal proof]]s demonstrating the [[consistency]], [[completeness]], and [[Decidability (logic)|decidability]] of particular [[formal system]]s. |
|||
Major results in metalogic include: |
|||
* Proof of the uncountability of the set of all subsets of the set of natural numbers ([[Cantor's theorem]] 1891) |
|||
* [[Löwenheim-Skolem theorem]] ([[Leopold Löwenheim]] 1915 and [[Thoralf Skolem]] 1919) |
|||
* Proof of the consistency of truth-functional [[Propositional calculus|propositional logic]] ([[Emil Post]] 1920) |
|||
* Proof of the semantic completeness of truth-functional propositional logic ([[Paul Bernays]] 1918),<ref name="reflections">Hao Wang, Reflections on Kurt Gödel</ref> ([[Emil Post]] 1920)<ref name="metalogic"/> |
|||
* Proof of the syntactic completeness of truth-functional propositional logic ([[Emil Post]] 1920)<ref name="metalogic"/> |
|||
* Proof of the decidability of truth-functional propositional logic ([[Emil Post]] 1920)<ref name="metalogic"/> |
|||
* Proof of the consistency of first order [[monadic predicate logic]] ([[Leopold Löwenheim]] 1915) |
|||
* Proof of the semantic completeness of first order monadic predicate logic ([[Leopold Löwenheim]] 1915) |
|||
* Proof of the decidability of first order monadic predicate logic ([[Leopold Löwenheim]] 1915) |
|||
* Proof of the consistency of first order predicate logic ([[David Hilbert]] and [[Wilhelm Ackermann]] 1928) |
|||
* Proof of the semantic completeness of first order [[predicate logic]] ([[Gödel's completeness theorem]] 1930) |
|||
* Proof of the undecidability of first order predicate logic ([[Church's theorem]] 1936) |
|||
* [[Gödel's first incompleteness theorem]] 1931 |
|||
* [[Gödel's second incompleteness theorem]] 1931 |
|||
* [[Tarski's undefinability theorem]] (Gödel and Tarski in the 1930s) |
|||
== See also == |
|||
{{Portal|Logic}} |
|||
* [[Metamathematics]] |
|||
== References == |
|||
<references/> |
|||
{{Logic}} |
|||
[[Category:Metalogic| ]] |
|||
[[Category:Mathematical logic]] |
|||
[[bg:Металогика]] |
|||
[[de:Metalogik]] |
|||
[[fa:فرامنطق]] |
|||
[[id:Metalogika]] |
|||
[[nl:Metalogica]] |
|||
[[pl:Metalogika]] |
|||
[[ru:Металогика]] |
|||
[[simple:Metalogic]] |
|||
[[sk:Metalogika]] |
|||
[[sv:Metalogik]] |
|||
[[uk:Металогіка]] |
|||
[[fr:Métalogique]] |
Revision as of 03:16, 21 May 2012
not reliable sources.
page must be deleted, end of story