Jump to content

Probability axioms

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Kolmogorov's axioms)

The standard probability axioms are the foundations of probability theory introduced by Russian mathematician Andrey Kolmogorov in 1933.[1] These axioms remain central and have direct contributions to mathematics, the physical sciences, and real-world probability cases.[2]

There are several other (equivalent) approaches to formalising probability. Bayesians will often motivate the Kolmogorov axioms by invoking Cox's theorem or the Dutch book arguments instead.[3][4]

Kolmogorov axioms

[edit]

The assumptions as to setting up the axioms can be summarised as follows: Let be a measure space with being the probability of some event , and . Then is a probability space, with sample space , event space and probability measure .[1]

First axiom

[edit]

The probability of an event is a non-negative real number:

where is the event space. It follows (when combined with the second axiom) that is always finite, in contrast with more general measure theory. Theories which assign negative probability relax the first axiom.

Second axiom

[edit]

This is the assumption of unit measure: that the probability that at least one of the elementary events in the entire sample space will occur is 1.

Third axiom

[edit]

This is the assumption of σ-additivity:

Any countable sequence of disjoint sets (synonymous with mutually exclusive events) satisfies

Some authors consider merely finitely additive probability spaces, in which case one just needs an algebra of sets, rather than a σ-algebra.[5] Quasiprobability distributions in general relax the third axiom.

Consequences

[edit]

From the Kolmogorov axioms, one can deduce other useful rules for studying probabilities. The proofs[6][7][8] of these rules are a very insightful procedure that illustrates the power of the third axiom, and its interaction with the prior two axioms. Four of the immediate corollaries and their proofs are shown below:

Monotonicity

[edit]

If A is a subset of, or equal to B, then the probability of A is less than, or equal to the probability of B.

Proof of monotonicity[6]

[edit]

In order to verify the monotonicity property, we set and , where and for . From the properties of the empty set (), it is easy to see that the sets are pairwise disjoint and . Hence, we obtain from the third axiom that

Since, by the first axiom, the left-hand side of this equation is a series of non-negative numbers, and since it converges to which is finite, we obtain both and .

The probability of the empty set

[edit]

In many cases, is not the only event with probability 0.

Proof of the probability of the empty set

[edit]

since ,

by applying the third axiom to the left-hand side (note is disjoint with itself), and so

by subtracting from each side of the equation.

The complement rule

[edit]

Proof of the complement rule

[edit]

Given and are mutually exclusive and that :

... (by axiom 3)

and, ... (by axiom 2)

The numeric bound

[edit]

It immediately follows from the monotonicity property that

Proof of the numeric bound

[edit]

Given the complement rule and axiom 1 :

Further consequences

[edit]

Another important property is:

This is called the addition law of probability, or the sum rule. That is, the probability that an event in A or B will happen is the sum of the probability of an event in A and the probability of an event in B, minus the probability of an event that is in both A and B. The proof of this is as follows:

Firstly,

. (by Axiom 3)

So,

(by ).

Also,

and eliminating from both equations gives us the desired result.

An extension of the addition law to any number of sets is the inclusion–exclusion principle.

Setting B to the complement Ac of A in the addition law gives

That is, the probability that any event will not happen (or the event's complement) is 1 minus the probability that it will.

Simple example: coin toss

[edit]

Consider a single coin-toss, and assume that the coin will either land heads (H) or tails (T) (but not both). No assumption is made as to whether the coin is fair or as to whether or not any bias depends on how the coin is tossed.[9]

We may define:

Kolmogorov's axioms imply that:

The probability of neither heads nor tails, is 0.

The probability of either heads or tails, is 1.

The sum of the probability of heads and the probability of tails, is 1.

See also

[edit]
  • Borel algebra – Class of mathematical sets
  • Conditional probability – Probability of an event occurring, given that another event has already occurred
  • Fully probabilistic design
  • Intuitive statistics – cognitive phenomenon where organisms use data to make generalizations and predictions about the world
  • Quasiprobability – Concept in statistics
  • Set theory – Branch of mathematics that studies sets
  • σ-algebra – Algebraic structure of set algebra

References

[edit]
  1. ^ a b Kolmogorov, Andrey (1950) [1933]. Foundations of the theory of probability. New York, US: Chelsea Publishing Company.
  2. ^ Aldous, David. "What is the significance of the Kolmogorov axioms?". David Aldous. Retrieved November 19, 2019.
  3. ^ Cox, R. T. (1946). "Probability, Frequency and Reasonable Expectation". American Journal of Physics. 14 (1): 1–10. Bibcode:1946AmJPh..14....1C. doi:10.1119/1.1990764.
  4. ^ Cox, R. T. (1961). The Algebra of Probable Inference. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.
  5. ^ Hájek, Alan (August 28, 2019). "Interpretations of Probability". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved November 17, 2019.
  6. ^ a b Ross, Sheldon M. (2014). A first course in probability (Ninth ed.). Upper Saddle River, New Jersey. pp. 27, 28. ISBN 978-0-321-79477-2. OCLC 827003384.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  7. ^ Gerard, David (December 9, 2017). "Proofs from axioms" (PDF). Retrieved November 20, 2019.
  8. ^ Jackson, Bill (2010). "Probability (Lecture Notes - Week 3)" (PDF). School of Mathematics, Queen Mary University of London. Retrieved November 20, 2019.
  9. ^ Diaconis, Persi; Holmes, Susan; Montgomery, Richard (2007). "Dynamical Bias in the Coin Toss" (PDF). SIAM Review. 49 (211–235): 211–235. Bibcode:2007SIAMR..49..211D. doi:10.1137/S0036144504446436. Retrieved 5 January 2024.

Further reading

[edit]